In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 4 pptx

56 304 0
In Search of Consistency: Ethics and Animals [Human–Animal Studies] Part 4 pptx

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống

Thông tin tài liệu

152 chapter four moral duty to respect the hunted animal” (P. Taylor, Unpublished 2). (“Inherent worth” is also discussed in chapters 1 and 2.) Taylor ascribes inherent worth to each entity that has “a good of their own,” to all those myriad entities that “can be made better or worse off ” (Respect 56, 75). For Taylor, having a good of one’s own makes an entity worthy of moral consideration, and moral consid- eration carries duties for moral agents (Respect 75). If an entity has inherent worth, then that being is worthy of moral consideration from moral agents. For Taylor, inherent worth indicates that moral agents have a prima facie duty to promote or preserve that entity’s good as an end in itself—for the sake of that entity (Respect 75). b. Teleology Taylor’s theory ascribes inherent worth to wild teleological entities. “Everything that is alive at this moment is the result of ancestors who displayed brilliant artifices to reproduce against nearly impos- sible odds” (Sagoff 15). While Western humans have excellent odds of finding enough food and avoiding predators, this is not the case for all creatures. Biological beings have a variety of needs; survival depends on how well they cope with their environment (Broom 90). In its simplest definition, teleology guides organisms to fulfill bio- logical needs so that they/we might succeed at the daunting task of survival (G. Williams 136). Ernest Nagel describes teleology as that which distinguishes “liv- ing from inanimate things,” and which specifically refers to “the apparently purposive character of living organisms” (276). He divides teleological statements into two types. First are goal ascriptions, which “state some outcome or goal toward which certain activities of an organism or of its parts are directed” (E. Nagel 277). For instance, the goal of pecking in woodpeckers is to find grubs. This form of teleology is “guided by a program” and “dependent on the existence of some endpoint or goal” (Mayr 48). Second are function ascrip- tions, which “make evident one role some item plays in a given sys- tem” (E. Nagel 315). This includes for example, “the heart that is built to pump the blood through the body, the kidneys that are built to eliminate the byproducts of protein metabolism, the intestinal tract that performs digestion and makes nutritional material available to the body,” and teeth that chew food and send the food down to the digestive tract (Mayr 49). Characteristic language of teleology includes function, purpose, goal, and behaviors intended to “bring about” a certain end (Mayr 39). paul taylor: bio-protectionism 153 Ernst Mayr discusses two other forms of teleology that apply to inanimate matter. First is a process “in which a definite end is reached strictly as a consequence of physical laws” (49). Gravity carries a baseball to the earth as dependably as it carries water to the seas. Laws of gravitation and thermodynamics frequently govern the unfold- ing of events on planet earth. “The entire process of cosmic evolu- tion, from the first big bang to the present time” is a direct result of physical laws such as these (Mayr 49). Finally, Mayr discusses a cosmic teleology, a form of teleology that Aristotle attributed to the cosmos as a whole. He did not under- stand evolution, yet as he studied life and the world around him he concluded that chance was not a viable explanation for what he wit- nessed. The world, he thought, must be guided by purpose. Christians seized on this Aristotelian concept, attributing the ultimate purpose to God. Mayr notes that this cosmic teleology is rejected by mod- ern science “without reservation. There is not and never was any program on the basis of which either cosmic or biological evolution has occurred” (50). Cosmic teleology is now understood to be the result of “selection forces generated by competition among individ- uals and species and by the colonization of new adaptive zones” (Mayr 50). Taylor’s teleology, consistent with thoughts of most other con- temporary thinkers, does not include inanimate forces. Taylor’s moral theory protects “any wild creature just in virtue of its being a mem- ber of a biotic community of a natural ecosystem” (Respect 79). Such teleological beings are not to be treated as a means to an end, but as ends in themselves with a value independent of any utility ascribed by human beings (Respect 57). While “animals may not actually be valued by humans as highly as other humans [are valued] this does not mean that animals do not have the same inherent [worth] as humans” (“Inherent” 17). In Taylor’s view the spotted sandpiper and the spotted hyena, the spider wasp and the spider crab all have inherent worth. For Taylor, teleology entails both internal functioning and exter- nal activities, both of which constantly work to maintain an organ- ism’s existence (Respect 121). Teleological entities have “interests” because they have a good that can be thwarted: “We have each a good of our own, and each of us, human and non-human alike, can be helped or hindered in the realization of that good” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 238). Like human beings, 154 chapter four other organisms are teleological centers of life. The constant tendency of their behavior and internal processes is patterned around the real- ization of their good. Although the content of our good and the means by which we pursue it may be vastly different from theirs, the teleo- logical order exemplified both in our lives and in theirs signifies a fun- damental reality common to all of us. (P. Taylor, Respect 157) Teleological entities pursue the realization of their interests, and Taylor asserts that to harm the good of a teleological entity thwarts interests and denies inherent worth (P. Taylor, Respect 71–72). Each living thing endeavors to maintain its existence. In this ongoing strug- gle for survival, the unique capacities of each teleological being jus- tify “the ascription of inherent worth to life in general” (“Inherent” 259–60). The essence of goal and function ascriptions—the essence of teleology—is survival. “The only thing that anything in nature is designed to accomplish is its own success” (G. Williams 156). Teleo- logical entities strive to persist genetically. c. Equal Moral Consideration Entities that have inherent worth are all equally deserving of moral consideration (P. Taylor, Respect 79). Anymals that have a good of their own, from the rhinoceros auklet to the elephant shrew, have moral standing. This moral standing carries corresponding duties for moral agents. Taylor asserts that because of teleology, because organisms “grow, respond to stimuli, reproduce, resist dying, assimilate, and use materials from their environment” in order to survive, we ought to respect their efforts and their lives (Scoville 121). There is a measure of equality in biological beings—all have adapted successfully and are able to survive in their particular environment (Gunn, “Traditional” 151). Taylor acknowledges this equality, and this remarkable endeavor that we are all engaged in, and requires human beings to regard “every entity which has a good of its own as possessing inherent worth—the same inherent worth, since none is superior to another” (Respect 155). 4. Moral Agents and Moral Patients In Taylor’s work, as in Regan’s, moral agents can be held morally accountable. In contrast, moral patients are not morally accountable; they cannot do right, nor can they do wrong. Also as in Regan’s Rights View, Taylor considers most humans to be moral agents, while anymals (and some humans) are moral patients—though he paul taylor: bio-protectionism 155 admits he cannot be certain about the moral status of anymals (Respect 14). Taylor’s definition of a moral agent includes the ability to form judgments about right and wrong; the ability to engage in moral deliberation, that is to consider and weigh moral rea- sons for and against various courses of conduct open to choice; the ability to make decisions on the basis of those reasons; the ability to exercise the necessary resolve and willpower to carry out those deci- sions; and the capacity to hold oneself answerable to others for fail- ing to carry them out. (Respect 14) 5. Rights Taylor introduces and discusses various types of rights in his theory of Respect for Nature. a. Legal Rights Taylor notes that nonhuman entities have legal rights in the Western world. He defines legal rights as entitlements established by law. He cites the Endangered Species Act and also laws that prohibit recre- ational killing of “game” anymals in certain places at certain times, as proof that both plants and anymals have legal rights (Respect 223). He notes that legal rights are distinct from moral rights. b. Moral Rights Taylor does not ascribe moral rights to anymals. He argues that moral rights, in contrast to legal rights, can only be ascribed to “per- sons.” For Taylor, a “person” is an entity that has interests and pur- poses, preferences and plans, a sense of personal identity over time, and makes autonomous choices or valuations (Respect 33–36). Addi- tionally, “persons” have self-respect, can exercise or enjoy rights, and hold others to account (Respect 246, 251). Taylor also asserts that “persons” are autonomous, rational beings who choose their own value system and direct their own lives on the basis of their value system (P. Taylor, Respect 36). Taylor does not find that anymals (or plants) fulfill the necessary set of criteria for “personhood,” and so he grants only human beings this status, a status that, in Taylor’s view, carries moral rights. In Taylor’s theory, bearers of moral rights “are acknowledged to have supreme authority over those conditions of their lives which are essential to preserving their personhood” (“Inherent” 26). Furthermore, for Taylor, moral rights require that one be a member of a community 156 chapter four of moral agents. Anymals do not have such supreme authority in Taylor’s view; he does not recognize them as “persons,” or as bear- ers of moral rights. c. Human Rights Taylor describes human rights as rooted in “human ethics based on respect for persons.” Taylor views human rights as central to the structure and function of societies (Respect 234). “The principle of respect for persons is built into the very structure of the moral com- munity and serves as the ultimate ground of the rules of duty within the domain of human ethics [and] serves as the foundation for universal human rights” (P. Taylor, Respect 39). Taylor writes that human rights belong “to all persons in virtue of their personhood Thus they are universal (belonging to every person) and equal (the same for all persons)” (“Inherent” 25). Basic human rights consist in a set of guaranteed opportunities and permissions which make it possible for one to (choose to) maintain oneself as a living organism and to seek those ends of interest that make up the central values of one’s self-determined conception of a meaningful life. Thus our basic rights set boundaries of inviolability, as it were, around the core of our existence. (“Inherent” 25) Taylor lists several human rights: • Physical security: the right to subsistence and security, including the “physical necessities of biological survival,” the right not to be killed, and the right of physical safety (Respect 235). • Liberty: the right to liberty entails “freedom from positive external constraints upon the pursuit of one’s permissible interests” (Respect 237). “Permissible” means those interests that do not infringe on the rights of others, or break a valid moral rule, including “the right to take effective steps to realize the goals we have set for ourselves, without hindrances or obstacles placed in our way by others”; we are “at liberty to pursue our good as we see fit,” but not necessarily to have our good realized (Respect 237–39). • Autonomy: the right to autonomy includes the right to self-deter- mination, which allows individuals to lead their own lives, “based on goals they set for themselves and values they have chosen for themselves [T]hey are accordingly self-directed and self-gov- erned beings” (Respect 239). paul taylor: bio-protectionism 157 Taylor asserts that human rights maintain the integrity of persons: “[W]e must conceive of rights as protecting those conditions essential to the rights-holder’s existence as the kind of being it is” (“Inherent” 27). For Taylor, those conditions essential to our welfare are those conditions to which we have a moral right. Taylor grants human autonomy, but insists on concurrent moral obligations. He asserts that morality assumes each person to be the “center of autonomous choice, living (or potentially capable of liv- ing) a way of life according to his or her own value-system,” and obligated to all other moral agents according to rules of ethics (Respect 37). Autonomy necessarily involves limits, and self-respect rather than self-interest forms the basis of human rights. Consequently, “where the preservation of the whole system of rights is at stake, it is under- stood that our rights can justifiably be overridden, with or without our consent” (“Inherent” 25–26). Taylor comes full circle back to legal rights. Moral rights become laws, Taylor explains, because “rational and autonomous persons” unanimously adopt such rules when they “give equal weight to every per- son’s value-system and at the same time make it possible for each to pursue the realization of his or her own value-system in ways compatible with everyone else’s similar pursuit” (Respect 38). Moral rights, according to Taylor, inevitably become law because it is in everyone’s best interest to secure, protect, and defend human rights with human laws. d. A Parallel Theory Taylor maintains that the language of moral rights cannot be applied to anymals and plants because this would imply that other living beings have rights in the same manner that humans have rights, which he insists they do not. He adds that moral rights (such as human rights) are not necessary for the protection of nonhuman entities, that his theory of environmental ethics offers nonpersons the same securities that human rights offer persons (Respect 254). As one might then expect, Taylor’s theory of environmental ethics parallels human ethics. He differentiates two categories of ethical conduct: human ethics and environmental ethics. The former is grounded in respect for persons, the later in respect for nature (Respect 26). Just as respect for persons is manifest in human rights, “rules of duty governing our treatment of the natural world and its inhab- itants” exemplify respect for nature (P. Taylor, “Ethics” 203). Taylor 158 chapter four asserts that there is no reason for anymals or plants to have moral rights if we adopt the environmental ethic of Respect for Nature. 6. Philosophical Principles and Standards Taylor explains the principles and standards to which both human and environmental ethics might be held. Moral rules must be • general in form, • universally applicable to all moral agents, • intended to be applied disinterestedly, • intended as normative for all moral agents, and • considered to override all nonmoral norms (Respect 27). Taylor rejects moral intuition on the grounds that it impedes the process of seeking ethical truths (Respect 23). C. Taylor’s Respect for Nature Taylor’s theory of environmental ethics consists of a belief system, attitude, and set of rules, the first of which leads to the second, which leads into the third. The “belief-system supports and makes intelli- gible the adopting of the attitude, and the rules and standards give concrete expression to that attitude in practical life” (Respect 44). Taylor describes four rules and five principles that offer guidance for the practical application of his environmental theory, but first he builds a foundation, which consists of the belief system and attitude central to Taylor’s theory of Respect for Nature. Taylor notes that an “outlook” cannot be proven true or false. He defends the biocentric outlook because the “beliefs that make up the content of the biocentric outlook are scientifically established” and “firmly rooted in the findings of the physical and biological sciences” (“In Defense” 240, Respect 160). A worldview stands or falls based on well-established criteria: comprehensiveness, coherence and inter- nal consistency, freedom from obscurity and semantic vacuity, and consistency with known empirical truths. Taylor holds the biocen- tric outlook up to this light and concludes that it is sound (Respect 158–61). paul taylor: bio-protectionism 159 1. Belief System—Biocentric Outlook An individual holds a belief system, which in turn supports a certain attitude. Taylor’s belief system, the biocentric outlook, has three core features. a. Interdependence “Each animal and plant in the natural world pursues its own good in its own way and therefore is similar, in that respect, to a human” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 237). Those who hold a biocentric outlook will view themselves as members of the “Earth’s Community of Life,” dependent for existence on the “biological system of nature” (P. Taylor, Respect 44). One who holds a biocentric outlook will recognize peo- ple as part of the earth’s vast interdependent community wherein each organism exists on the same terms as each other living organism (P. Taylor, Respect 99). “The biocentric outlook recognizes a natural world where each species, including humans, is an integral, inter- dependent element, and the welfare of each living thing is “deter- mined not only by the physical conditions of its environment but also by its relations to other living things” (P. Taylor, Respect 100). In Taylor’s theory, all life is ecologically interdependent. The un- ending “reality and universality of this condition throughout the whole realm of life on Earth” unites “humans and non-humans in a single system of relationships” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 239). Realizing this simple truth of our existence is basic to the biocentric outlook. To elucidate the interconnected nature of existence on planet earth, Taylor turns to teleology. The biocentric outlook recognizes each organism—plant and anymal—as a unique goal-oriented being “pur- suing its own good in its own unique way. [Each] living thing is conceived as a unified system of organized activity, the constant ten- dency of which is to preserve its existence by protecting and promoting its well-being” (Respect 45). The biocentric outlook does not describe what any given entity’s well-being might entail. Some—insects in particular—sacrifice indi- viduals for the sake of species, for the furthering of group goals, revealing some of the many diverse methods by which living beings “realize their own biological potentialities” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 238). Each species is unique, and each teleological entity carries out “its biological functions according to the laws of its species-specific nature” 160 chapter four (P. Taylor, “Ethics” 210). The good of both plants and anymals re- quires that their “ecological equilibrium” be maintained; the same holds true for the well-being of humans (P. Taylor, “Ethics” 209). A jagua- rundi and an olive-sided flycatcher pursue their goods in different ways. The earth’s abundance of species holds a vast array of “goods” they hope to satisfy, and a plethora of methods for achieving satisfaction. b. Equality Individuals who hold Taylor’s biocentric outlook will not place humans either at the center or at the top of the natural order. This makes perfect sense when viewed in light of our interconnected nature. We cannot be separate or above those on whom we are dependent for our very existence. Taylor’s vision “requires humans to treat other creatures in such a way that there is no bias in favor of humans just because they are human” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 241). Morality rooted in the bio- centric outlook entails “a disposition to ascribe to wild animals and plants the same inherent worth which we attribute to our fellow humans, and to regard them as deserving of equal consideration” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 240). The biocentric outlook holds that, regardless of our animal nature, it is never acceptable to destroy a life “merely on the grounds that it would benefit human beings” (Regan, “Nature” 32). In short, the biocentric outlook entails “species impartiality,” which means “all living beings are judged to be equally worthy of moral concern and consideration” (Respect 46). To “accept the [biocentric] outlook is to understand the place of humans in the domain of life on Earth as one of fundamental equality with other members an equality that extends to all forms of life in our planet’s natural ecosystems” (P. Taylor, “In Defense” 240). c. Insider’s Perspective The third expectation of Taylor’s biocentric outlook is that we view other beings from the reference points of those other beings—from a point of view that sees each entity’s shared interest in “survival, health, and well-being” (Respect 124). If we are to understand the life of hagfish, we must attempt to move behind their eyes, into their skin, and see the world from their vantage point. This outlook offers “the most complete realization, cognitively and imaginatively, of what it is to be that particular individual”; the biocentric outlook allows us to “let the reality of another’s life enter the world of our own con- sciousness” (Respect 128). paul taylor: bio-protectionism 161 2. Attitude—Respect for Nature Taylor’s biocentric outlook “underlies, supports, and makes intelligi- ble” the attitude of respect for nature, and is critical to achieving respect for nature (Respect 167). Virtues are important to Taylor’s theory because the attitudes that lead one to care about the environ- ment are rooted in human character (Respect 199). Virtues such as conscientiousness, integrity, courage, perseverance, benevolence, sym- pathy, impartiality, trustworthiness, and fairness are therefore criti- cal to Respect for Nature. An individual with these virtues will accept environmental ethics in the same way that most people accept human ethics—as a fundamental and formative aspect of life. Those who hold an attitude of respect for nature will not harm or interfere with the world around them. They will honor “the nat- ural status of wild living things” and strive to preserve “their exis- tence as part of the order of nature” (P. Taylor, Respect 81). Those who respect nature will use reason to determine which actions are rooted in respect for nature, and they will strive for policies and practices that preserve natural ecosystems. One who holds an attitude of respect for nature will be emotionally engaged so as to feel pleased or displeased according to whether or not events uphold or damage the earth’s natural ecosystems (P. Taylor, Respect 81–83). But as in Kant’s ethical theory, actions must be moti- vated by ethical obligations, not personal affection. Actions that main- tain natural ecosystems do not express respect for nature unless they are motivated by a respect for the inherent worth of living organ- isms. Furthermore, actions that express respect for nature must be done “as a matter of moral principle” (P. Taylor, Respect 85). Moral imperatives guide individuals who respect nature, and such people pursue ethical actions in a disinterested fashion (P. Taylor, Respect 92). In Taylor’s theory, intentions matter. [P]eople show genuine respect for nature only when they act or decline to act out of consideration and concern for the good of wild living things To express in practical life one’s respect for nature, one’s intentions and aims must be directed toward not interfering with or harming ani- mals and plants in natural ecosystems and to preserving their wild sta- tus for their sake. Having those aims and intentions as one’s ultimate ends is essential to having true respect for nature. (Respect 84–85) [...]... selection and participates in a struggle for existence, neither of which is true for machines When a living entity dies, parts disintegrate, whereas the parts of machines do not The telos of a machine is extrinsic, imposed by human beings, whereas the telos of living entities is intrinsic (theological explanations aside) (Rollin 40 ) Living organisms are “problem-solving complexes” as distinct from machines... without indicating that dangerous individuals have a lesser inherent worth (Respect 267) b Proportionality Proportionality (and the next principle, that of minimum wrong) applies to cases that involve basic interests of moral subjects and nonbasic interests of persons Taylor defines “nonbasic” interests as interests that promote the good of an entity, and “basic” interests as those that promote the good of. .. might cause the extinction of that species To save individuals of a species is in fact to save that species Furthermore, caring for individuals, in most instances, is likely to favor rare or endangered species Killing a member of a rare species (or allowing it to die) adds, proportionally, greater stress to the remaining members For instance, the difficulty of finding a mate in a dwindling species is significantly... undesirable intrusion into the natural world c Fidelity Fidelity forbids gaining an entity’s trust in order to deceive and gain advantage for immoral reasons We are required to maintain integrity in our actions so that the expectations of anymals are fulfilled Taylor targets hunting, trapping, and fishing as particularly deceitful Such actions intentionally deceive anymals with calls, shiny lures, and scents... environmentalists object to releasing such critters into the wild A species, like any other thing with interests, has an interest in maintaining itself as a coherent, integrated, functional ongoing whole with a particular self-identity This requires more than just survival It is a matter of what survives Relating to a particular sort of environment is part of the self-identity of a species and pressure from the... means that individuals have an interest in the demise of other members within their own species Thus deer and zebra do have an interest 172 chapter four in having predators kill others of their kind It is a misrepresentation to suggest that the zebra or deer eaten by a big cat has an interest in being eaten In fact, individual members of a species continue to compete with one another even when extinction... greater reduction in the chances that their offspring will produce offspring (Agar 41 3– 14) Concern for individuals favors individuals who are members of a rare species because of the heightened impact of one loss on all remaining members Thus, favoring individuals also favors rare species Control over the fate of populations “brings with it some responsibility for the welfare of the individuals of which they... to be eaten atop homes at extreme altitudes in Nepal In the Arctic, and even in high mountainous regions in China, Tibet, and Nepal, people import food staples such as sugar and flour The Inuit people of northwestern Alaska drink tea from India and nursing milk from cows in Wisconsin They eat bakery bread, ice cream, and hamburgers with French fries, none of which are locally produced How can anyone... Captive-bred beings bring human intervention with them into any ecosystem into which they are released Taylor’s acceptance of captive-bred anymals into wild ecosystems contradicts his insistence on protecting only “natural” entities—entities whose relations are unaffected by human intervention Captive breeding is inherently “unnatural” and therefore harms the integrity of wild individuals and species, and some... regard to individuals (Mayr 43 ) In this case species and individuals would merely be pawns for genes that are endlessly striving to reproduce themselves, using individual organisms and species for their purposes “If genes are the targets of selection, then the preservation of genes is the most fundamental function or purpose of natural things and an ethic grounded in the maintenance of biological interests . entity’s well-being might entail. Some—insects in particular—sacrifice indi- viduals for the sake of species, for the furthering of group goals, revealing some of the many diverse methods by which living beings “realize. system, attitude, and set of rules, the first of which leads to the second, which leads into the third. The “belief-system supports and makes intelli- gible the adopting of the attitude, and the rules and standards. entity’s shared interest in “survival, health, and well-being” (Respect 1 24) . If we are to understand the life of hagfish, we must attempt to move behind their eyes, into their skin, and see the world

Ngày đăng: 05/08/2014, 21:23

Từ khóa liên quan

Tài liệu cùng người dùng

  • Đang cập nhật ...

Tài liệu liên quan