The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics Part 30 potx

10 374 0
The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics Part 30 potx

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

Thông tin tài liệu

Burkhardt, Armin. 1996. Zwischen Poesie und O ¨ konomie: Die Metonymie als se- mantisches Prinzip. Zeitschrift fu ¨ r Germanistische Linguistik 24: 175–94. Copestake, Ann, and Ted Briscoe. 1995. Semi-productive polysemy and sense extension. Journal of Semantics 12: 15–67. Croft, William. 1993. The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and me- tonymies. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 335–70. Croft, William. 2001. Radical construction grammar: Syntactic theory in typological per- spective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cruse, D. Alan. 2000. Meaning in language: An introduction to semantics and pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dirven, Rene ´ . 1993. Metonymy and metaphor: Different mental strategies of con- ceptualisation. Leuvense Bijdragen 82: 1–28. Dirven, Rene ´ , and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds. 2002. Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Dubois, Jacques, Francis Edeline, Jean-Marie Klinkenberg, Philippe Minguet, Franc¸ois Pire, and Madelin Trinon. 1970. Rhe ´ torique ge ´ ne ´ rale. Paris: Larousse. Fauconnier, Gilles. 1985. Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural lan- guage. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994) Feyaerts, Kurt. 1999. Metonymic hierarchies: The conceptualization of stupidity in German idiomatic expressions. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 309–32. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Feyaerts, Kurt. 2000. Refining the inheritance hypothesis: Interaction between metaphoric and metonymic hierarchies. In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cognitive perspective 59–78. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Geeraerts, Dirk. 1988. Cognitive grammar and the history of lexical semantics. In Brygida Rudzka-Ostyn, ed., Topics in cognitive linguistics 647–77. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Geeraerts, Dirk. 1994. Metonymy. In R. E. Asher, ed., The encyclopedia of language and linguistics 5: 2477–78. Oxford: Pergamon. Geeraerts, Dirk. 2002. The interaction of metaphor and metonymy in composite expres- sions. In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 435–65. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Gibbs, Raymond W., Jr. 1994. The poetics of mind: Figurative thought, language, and un- derstanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gibbs, Raymond W., Jr. 1999. Speaking and thinking with metonymy. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 61–76. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Goldberg, Adele E. 1995. Constructions: A construction grammar approach to argument structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Goossens, Louis. 1990. Metaphtonymy: The interaction of metaphor and metonymy in expressions for linguistic actions. Cognitive Linguistics 1: 323–40. Goossens, Louis. 1999. Metonymic bridges in modal shifts. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 193–210. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Goossens, Louis. 2000. Patterns of meaning extension, ‘‘parallel chaining,’’ subjectification, and modal shifts. In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cognitive perspective 149–69. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Goossens, Louis. 2002. Metaphtonymy: The interaction of metaphor and metonymy in expressions for linguistic action. In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 349–77. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. 260 klaus-uwe panther and linda l. thornburg Grady, Joseph. 1997. Foundations of meaning: Primary metaphors and primary scenes. PhD dissertation, University of California at Berkeley. Grady, Joseph, and Christopher Johnson. 2002. Converging evidence for the notions of subscene and primary scene. In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 533–54. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Grice, H. Paul. 1975 . Logic and conversation. In Peter Cole and Jerry Morgan, eds., Syntax and semantics, vol. 3, Speech acts 41–58. New York: Academic Press. Heine, Bernd, Ulrike Claudi, and Friederike Hu ¨ nnemeyer. 1991. Grammaticalization: A conceptual framework. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hopper, Paul J., and Elizabeth Closs Traugott. 1993. Grammaticalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (2nd ed., 2003) Jakobson, Roman. [1956] 1971. Two aspects of language and two types of aphasic distur- bances. In Roman Jakobson and Morris Halle, eds., Fundamentals of language 67–96. The Hague: Mouton. Kleiber, Georges. 1995. Polyse ´ mie, transferts de sens et me ´ tonymie inte ´ gre ´ e. Folia Lin- guistica 29: 105–32. Koch, Peter. 1999. Frame and contiguity: On the cognitive bases of metonymy and certain types of word formation. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 139–67. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Ko ¨ vecses, Zolta ´ n. 1986. Metaphors of anger, pride and love: A lexical approach to the study of concepts. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Ko ¨ vecses, Zolta ´ n. 1995. Anger: Its language, conceptualisation, and physiology in the light of cross-cultural evidence. In John R. Taylor and Robert E. MacLaury, eds., Lan- guage and the cognitive construal of the world 181–96. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Books. Lakoff, George, and Mark Turner. 1989. More than cool reason: A field guide to poetic metaphor. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Langacker, Ronald W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive grammar. Vol. 1, Theoretical pre- requisites. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Langacker, Ronald W. 1993. Reference-point constructions. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 1–38. Langacker, Ronald W. 2000 . Grammar and conceptualization. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Levinson, Stephen C. 2000. Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Nerlich, Brigitte, David D. Clarke, and Zazie Todd. 1999. ‘‘Mummy, I like being a sand- wich’’: Metonymy in language acquisition. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 362–83. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Niemeier, Susanne. 2000. Straight from the heart—metonymic and metaphorical explo- rations. In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cog- nitive perspective 195–213. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Nikiforidou, Kiki. 1999. Nominalizations, metonymy, and lexicographic practice. In Leon G. Stadler and Christoph Eyrich, eds., Issues in cognitive linguistics 141–63. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Norrick, Neal R. 1981. Semiotic principles in semantic theory. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1978. The pragmatics of reference. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club. metonymy 261 Nunberg, Geoffrey. 1995. Transfers of meaning. Journal of Semantics 17: 109–32. Panther, Klaus-Uwe. 2001. Syntactic control. In Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes, eds., International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences 15397–401. New York: Elsevier. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Gu ¨ nter Radden. 1999a. Introduction. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 1–14. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds. 1999b. Metonymy in language and thought. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 1998. A cognitive approach to inferencing in conversation. Journal of Pragmatics 30: 755–69. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 1999. The potentiality for actuality metonymy in English and Hungarian. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 333–57. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 2000. The effect for cause metonymy in English grammar. In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Metaphor and metonymy at the cross- roads: A cognitive perspective 215–31. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 2002. The roles of metaphor and metonymy in English -er nominals. In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 279–319. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 2003a. Introduction: On the nature of con- ceptual metonymy. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Linda Thornburg, eds., Metonymy and pragmatic inferencing 1–20. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg. 2003b. Metonymy and lexical aspect in English and French. Jezikoslovlje 4: 71–101. Panther, Klaus-Uwe, and Linda Thornburg, eds. 2003c. Metonymy and pragmatic in- ferencing. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Papafragou, Anna. 1996. Figurative language and the semantics-pragmatics distinction. Language and Literature 5: 179–93. Paul, Hermann. [1880] 1975. Prinzipien der Sprachgeschichte.Tu ¨ bingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag. Pe ´ rez Herna ´ ndez, Lorena, and Francisco Jose ´ Ruiz de Mendoza. 2002. Grounding, se- mantic motivation, and conceptual interaction in indirect directive speech acts. Journal of Pragmatics 34: 259–84. Pustejovsky, James. 1991. The generative lexicon. Computational Linguistics 17: 409–41. Pustejovsky, James. 1993. Type coercion and lexical selection. In James Pustejovsky, ed., Semantics and the lexicon 73–96. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer. Radden, Gu ¨ nter. 2000. How metonymic are metaphors? In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Met- aphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cognitive perspective 93–108. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Radden, Gu ¨ nter. 2002. How metonymic are metaphors? In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 407–34. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Radden, Gu ¨ nter, and Zolta ´ nKo ¨ vecses. 1999. Towards a theory of metonymy. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 17–59. Am- sterdam: John Benjamins. Riemer, Nick. 2002. When is a metonymy no longer a metonymy? In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and metonymy in comparison and contrast 379–406. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. 262 klaus-uwe panther and linda l. thornburg Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ . 2000. The role of mappings and domains in understanding metonymy. In Antonio Barcelona, ed., Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads: A cognitive perspective 109–32. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ , and Jose ´ Luis Otal Campo. 2002. Metonymy, grammar, and communication. Albolote, Granada: Editorial Comares. Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ , and Olga Isabel Dı ´ ez Velasco. 2002. Patterns of conceptual interaction. In Rene ´ Dirven and Ralf Po ¨ rings, eds., Metaphor and me- tonymy in comparison and contrast 489–532. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ , and Olga Isabel Dı ´ ez Velasco. 2004. Metonymic motivation in anaphoric reference. In Gu ¨ nter Radden and Klaus-Uwe Panther, eds., Studies in linguistic motivation 293–320. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ , and Lorena Pe ´ rez Herna ´ ndez. 2001. Metonymy and grammar: Motivation, constraints and interactions. Language & Communication 21: 321–57. Ruiz de Mendoza Iba ´ n ˜ ez, Francisco Jose ´ , and Lorena Pe ´ rez Herna ´ ndez. 2003. Cognitive operations and pragmatic implication. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Linda Thornburg, eds., Metonymy and pragmatic inferencing 23–49. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Ruwet, Nicolas. 1975. Synecdoques et me ´ tonymies. Poe ´ tique 6: 371–88. Schofer, Peter, and Donald Rice. 1977. Metaphor, metonymy, and synecdoche revis(it)ed. Semiotica 21: 121–47. Searle, John. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Searle, John. 1975. Indirect speech acts. In Peter Cole and Jerry Morgan, eds., Speech acts 59–82. New York: Academic Press. Seto, Ken-ichi. 1999. Distinguishing metonymy from synecdoche. In Klaus-Uwe Panther and Gu ¨ nter Radden, eds., Metonymy in language and thought 91–120. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Song, Nam Sun. 1997. Metaphor and metonymy. In Robyn Carston and Seiji Uchida, eds., Relevance Theory: Applications and implications 87–104. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Stirling, Lesley. 1996. Metonymy and anaphora. In Belgian Journal of Linguistics 10: 69–88. Sweetser, Eve. 1991. From etymology to pragmatics: Metaphorical and cultural aspects of semantic structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Talmy, Leonard. 2000. Toward a cognitive semantics. Vol. 2, Typology and process in concept structuring. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Thornburg, Linda, and Klaus Panther. 1997. Speech act metonymies. In Wolf-Andreas Liebert, Gisela Redeker, and Linda Waugh, eds., Discourse and perspectives in cognitive linguistics 201–19. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Traugott, Elizabeth Closs, and Ekkehard Ko ¨ nig. 1991. The semantics-pragmatics of grammaticalization revisited. In Elizabeth Closs Traugott and Bernd Heine, eds., Approaches to grammaticalization 1: 189–218. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Ullmann, Stephen. 1951. The principles of semantics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Ullmann, Stephen. 1962. Semantics: An introduction to the science of meaning. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. van Eemeren, Frans H., Rob Grootendorst, Ralph H. Johnson, Christian Plantin, Charles A. Willard, David Zarefsky, J. Anthony Blair, A. Francisca Snoeck Henkemans, Erik Krabbe, John H. Woods, and Douglas Walton. 1996. Fundamental argumentation theory: A handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. metonymy 263 chapter 11 ATTENTION PHENOMENA leonard talmy 1. Introduction 1.1. Content of the Study This chapter introduces new work on the fundamental attentional system of lan- guage (Talmy, forthcoming), while in part providing a framework in which prior linguistic work on attention can be placed. In a speech situation, a hearer may at- tend to the linguistic expression produced by a speaker, to the conceptual content represented by that expression, and to the context at hand. But not all of this ma- terial appears uniformly in the foreground of the hearer’s attention. Rather, various portions or aspects of the expression, content, and context have differing degrees of salience (see also Schmid, this volume, chapter 5). Such differences are only par- tially due to any intrinsically greater interest of certain elements over others. More fundamentally, language has an extensive system that assigns different degrees of salience to the parts of an expression or of its reference or of the context. In terms of the speech participants, the speaker employs this system in formulating an expres- sion; the hearer, largely on the basis of such formulations, allocates his or her at- tention in a particular way over the material of these domains. This attentional system in language includes a large number of basic factors, the ‘‘building blocks’’ of the system, with over fifty identified to date. Each factor involves a particular linguistic mechanism that increases or decreases attention on a certain type of linguistic entity. The mechanisms employed fall into some ten categories, most with subcategories. The type of linguistic entity whose degree of salience is determined by the factors is usually the semantic referent of a constituent, but other types occur, including the phonological shape of a constituent or the vocal delivery of the utterance. Each factor contrasts a linguistic circumstance in which attention is increased with a complementary circumstance in which it is decreased. A speaker can use a factor for either purpose—or in some cases for both at the same time. For some factors, increased attention on a linguistic entity is regularly accompanied by additional cognitive effects, such as distinctness, clarity, and sig- nificance, while decreased attention correlates with such converse effects as meldedness, vagueness, and ordinariness. The bulk of this chapter, section 2, pres- ents in highly excerpted form some of the attentional factors in their taxonomy. Although able to act alone, the basic factors also regularly combine and interact—whether in a single constituent, over a sentence, or through a discourse— to produce further attentional effects. Several such factor patterns are presented in abbreviated form in section 3. Many further aspects of language’s attentional system cannot be examined in this short chapter, but a few can be touched on here to give a fuller sense of the system. First, language-specific and typological differences occur in the use of attentional devices.Foralanguage-specificexample,someindividuallanguages(likeTamil)mani- fest factor Ca1 (see section 2.3) by using special morphemes to mark an adjacent constituent for foregrounding as topic or focus. Other languages (like English) do not use this mechanism at all. For a typological example, sign languages (see Talmy 2003b) appear to differ systematically from spoken languages in the use of a special mechanism for attentional disregard. To illustrate with American Sign Language (ASL), consider that I want to sign that a particular wall was architecturally moved farther out to enlarge a room. To represent the wall in its initial position, I begin the sign by holding my hands horizontally before me joined at the fingertips, with the flattened hands oriented vertically, palms toward myself. If the wall was physically moved along the floor while still standing, I would then move my hands horizontally away from myself with a steady deliberative movement. But the wall may instead have been removed and set up again at the more distant position. In that case, I now move my hands through a quick up-and-down arc, in effect showing them ‘‘jump’’ into the new more distant position. This quick arc-gesture signals that one is to dis- regard the spatial path that the hands are seen to follow and to take into consideration only the initial and final hand positions. Thus, this gesture can be regarded as a linguistic form with the function of calling for reduced attention to—in fact, for the disregard of—the path of the hands, which would otherwise be understood as a semantically relevant constituent. In addition to individual mechanisms of this last type, signed languages also have unique factor combinations. In ASL, for example, the nondominant hand can sign a specific topic and then be held fixed in position throughout the remainder of the clause as the dominant hand signs the comment (see Liddell 2003). That is, the nondominant hand maintains some of the viewer’s background attention on the identity of the topic, even as the dominant hand at- tracts the viewer’s attentional foreground to certain particulars of content. No ob- vious counterparts of these attentional devices occur in spoken languages. attention phenomena 265 Next, in the developing theoretical account of the attention system in language, some broad properties are already evident. For example, in terms of the qualities of attention per se, linguistic attention functions as a gradient, not as a dichotomous all-or-none phenomenon. The particular level of attention on a linguistic entity is set in terms of foregrounding or backgrounding relative to a baseline for the entity, rather than absolutely on a zero-based scale. And the linguistic aspects realized in the course of a discourse range along a gradient of ‘‘access to attention,’’ from ones with ‘‘interruptive’’ capacity, able to supplant whatever else is currently highest in atten- tion, to ones that basically remain unconscious. Further, in terms of attentional or- ganization, a number of the factors and their combinations accord with—perhaps fall out of—certain more general principles. By one such principle, attention tends to be more on the reference of some linguistic material—that is, on its semantic content— than on the form or structure of the material. And by a related principle, attention tends to be more on higher-level units of such content than on lower-level units. For example, attention is characteristically more on the overall literal meaning of a sen- tence than on the meanings of its individual words, and still more on the contextual import of that sentence’s meaning than on the literal meaning of the sentence. Finally, the attentional properties found in language appear to have both com- monalities and differences with attentional properties in other cognitive systems. An example of commonality is that greater magnitude along a cognitive parameter tends to attract greater attention to the entity manifesting it. This is seen both in language, say, for stronger stress on a linguistic constituent, and in visual perception, say, for large size or bright color of a viewed object. On the other hand, one mechanism in the attentional system of language is the use of special morphemes—for example, topic and focus markers—dedicated to the task of directing attention to the referent of an adjacent constituent. But the perceptual modalities appear to have little that is com- parable. Contrariwise, abrupt change along any sensory parameter is one of the main mechanisms in the perceptual modalities for attracting attention to the stimulus exhibiting it. But it has a minimal role in the attentional system of language. Thus, the larger study, which this chapter only introduces, covers the linguistic system of attentional factors and their patterns of interaction, a theoretical frame- work that includes the universal and typological aspects of this system, the general principles that the system is based on, and a comparison between this linguistic attentional system and that of other cognitive modalities. 1.2. Context of the Study Much previous linguistic work has involved the issue of attention or salience. Areas within such work are familiar under terms like topic and focus (e.g., Lambrecht 1994), focal attention (e.g., Tomlin 1995), activation (e.g., Givo ´ n 1990;Chafe1994), proto- type theory (e.g., Lakoff 1987), frame semantics (e.g., Fillmore 1976, 1982), profiling (e.g., Langacker 1987), and deictic center (e.g., Zubin and Hewitt 1995). My research on attention has included: the relative salience of the ‘‘Figure’’ and the ‘‘Ground’’ in 266 leonard talmy a represented situation (Talmy 1972, 1978a, 2000a: chapter 5); the ‘‘windowing’’ of attention on one or more selected portions of a represented scene, with attentional backgrounding of the ‘‘gapped’’ portions (Talmy 1976, 1983, 1995b, 1996b, 2000a: chapter 4); the attentional backgrounding versus foregrounding of concepts when expressed by closed-class (grammatical) forms versus by open-class (lexical) forms (Talmy 1978c, 1988b, 2000a: chapter 1); the ‘‘level’’ of attention set either on the whole of a scene or on its componential makeup (Talmy 1988b, 2000a: chapter 1); the differential attention on the ‘‘Agonist’’ and the ‘‘Antagonist,’’ the two entities in a force-dynamic opposition (Talmy 1988a, 2000a: chapter 7); ‘‘fictive motion,’’ in which a hearer is linguistically directed to sweep his or her focus of attention over the contours of a static scene (Talmy 1996a, 2000a: chapter 2); the backgrounding versus foregrounding of a concept when it is expressed in the verb complex versus by a nom- inal complement (Talmy 1985, 2000b: chapter 1); the backgrounding versus fore- grounding of a proposition when it is expressed by a subordinate clause versus by a main clause (Talmy 1978b, 1991, 2000a: chapter 6); the conscious as opposed to unconscious processes in the acquisition, manifestation, and imparting of cultural patterns (Talmy 1995a, 2000b: chapter 7); and attentional differences between spoken and signed language (Talmy 2003a, 2003b). However, the present study may be the first with the aim of developing a systematic framework within which to place all such prior findings—together with a number of new findings—about linguistic attention. In fact, this study is perhaps the first to recognize that the linguistic phenomena across this whole range do all pertain to the same single cognitive system of attention. The theoretical orientation of this study is, of course, that of Cognitive Lin- guistics. This linguistic approach is centered on the patterns in which and the pro- cesses by which conceptual content is organized in language. Cognitive Linguistics addresses this linguistic structuring of conception not only with respect to basic physical categories like space and time, force and causation, but also with respect to cognitive categories—the ideational and affective categories ascribed to sentient agents. These forms of conceptual structuring fall into several extensive classes, what I termed ‘‘schematic systems’’ (Talmy 2000a: chapter 1). One such system is that of ‘‘configurational structure,’’ which comprises the schematic structuring or geometric delineations in space or time (or other qualitative domains) that lin- guistic forms can specify (Talmy 2000a: chapters 1–3; 2000b: chapters 1–4). Another schematic system is ‘‘force dynamics,’’ which covers the structural representation of two entities interacting energetically with respect to opposition to a force, re- sistance to opposition, and overcoming of resistance, as well as to blockage, hin- drance, support, and causation (Talmy 2000a: chapters 7–8). And a third schematic system is that of ‘‘cognitive states and processes,’’ which includes the struc- tural representation of volition and intention, expectation and affect, and per- spective and attention (Talmy 2000a: chapters 1, 4, 5, 8). Thus, the present study of attention is an elaboration of one subportion within the extensive conceptual structuring system of language. In turn, the properties that attention is found to have in language can be compared with those of attention as it operates in other cognitive systems, such as in the various perceptual modalities, in the affect system, attention phenomena 267 in the reasoning/inferencing system, and in motor control. This kind of compar- ative procedure was introduced in Talmy (2000a), designated as the ‘‘overlapping systems model of cognitive organization.’’ Accordingly, it is assumed that the findings on attention in language will enable corroborative investigation by the methods of other fields of cognitive science, including the experimental techniques of psycholinguistics, the brain-imaging techniques of cognitive neuroscience, and the simulation techniques of artificial intelligence. The present study can thus help to develop a framework within which attentional findings from a range of research disciplines can be coordinated and ultimately integrated. 2. Some Linguistic Factors That Set Strength of Attention 2.1. Factors Involving Properties of the Morpheme (A) A morpheme is here quite generally understood to be any minimal linguistic form with an associated meaning. This thus includes not only simplex morphemes, but also idioms and constructions (e.g., the English auxiliary-subject inversion meaning ‘if’). Formal Properties of the Morpheme (Aa) Factor Aa1: Expression in One or Another Lexical Category A concept tends to be more or less salient in accordance with the lexical category of the form representing the concept. First, open-class categories in general lend more salience than closed-class categories. Further, within open-class categories, nouns may tend to outrank verbs while, within closed-class categories, forms with pho- nological substance may tend to outrank forms lacking it. Accordingly, lexical categories may exhibit something of the following salience hierarchy: open-class (N > V) > closed-class (phonological > aphonological) Only the open-class/closed-class contrast is illustrated here. Consider a case where essentially the same concept can be represented both by a closed-class form and by an open-class form. Thus, English tense is typically represented for a verb in a finite clause by a closed-class form, either an inflection or a modal, as in (1a) with an -ed for the past and (1b) with an -s or will for the future. But a nominal in a prepositional phrase cannot indicate tense in that way. If relative time is to be indicated here, one must resort to open-class forms, as in (2a), with the adjectives 268 leonard talmy previous to mark the past and (2b) with upcoming to mark the future. The concepts of relative time seem much more salient when expressed by adjectives than by closed-class forms (see Talmy 2000a: chapter 1). (1) a. When he arrived, b. When he arrives/will arrive, (2) a. On his previous arrival, b. On his upcoming arrival, Factor Aa2: Degree of Morphological Autonomy The term ‘‘degree of morphological autonomy’’ here refers to the grammatical status of a morpheme as free or bound. A concept tends to receive greater attention—and abetted by that attention, greater distinctness and clarity—when it is represented by a free morpheme than by a bound morpheme. Thus, the English free verb root ship and the bound verb root -port have approximately the same sense in their concrete usages, ‘convey bulky objects by vehicle over geographic distances’, and they appear in constructions with comparable meanings, such as ship in, ship out, ship away, ship across, and import, export, deport, transport. However, because, at least in part, of the difference in morphological autonomy of these two verb roots, ship foregrounds its concept with clarity and distinctness to a greater degree than - port does with its otherwise similar concept. Componential Properties of the Morpheme (Ab) Factor Ab1: Solo versus Joint Expression of a Component in a Morpheme When a concept constitutes the sole and entire referent of a morpheme, it tends to have greater salience and individuated attention, but when it is conflated together with other concepts in a morpheme’s reference, it tends to be more backgrounded and to meld with the other concepts. For example, the concepts ‘parent’ and ‘sister’ each receive greater individual attention when expressed alone in the separate mor- phemes parent and sister ,asinone of my parents’ sisters. But they receive less indi- vidual attention when expressed together in the single morpheme aunt,asinone of my aunts. Factor Ab2: The Ensemble versus the Individual Components of a Morpheme’s Meaning In general, a language user directs more attention to the combination or ensemble of the semantic components that make up the reference of a morpheme than to the individual components themselves. That is, more attention is on the Gestalt whole of a morpheme’s meaning than on its parts. Even where the components are all essential to the morpheme’s use, a speaker or hearer is typically little aware of them, attending instead to their synthesis. attention phenomena 269 . investigation by the methods of other fields of cognitive science, including the experimental techniques of psycholinguistics, the brain-imaging techniques of cognitive neuroscience, and the simulation. remainder of the clause as the dominant hand signs the comment (see Liddell 2003). That is, the nondominant hand maintains some of the viewer’s background attention on the identity of the topic,. extension. Journal of Semantics 12: 15–67. Croft, William. 1993. The role of domains in the interpretation of metaphors and me- tonymies. Cognitive Linguistics 4: 335–70. Croft, William. 2001.

Ngày đăng: 03/07/2014, 01:20

Từ khóa liên quan

Tài liệu cùng người dùng

  • Đang cập nhật ...

Tài liệu liên quan