Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống
1
/ 27 trang
THÔNG TIN TÀI LIỆU
Thông tin cơ bản
Định dạng
Số trang
27
Dung lượng
245,87 KB
Nội dung
–: theRomanticappropriationofKant (II): Schelling , , Few people in modern philosophy rose faster in public esteem and estab- lished a more celebrated career than F. W. J. Schelling. Born in southern Germany, in W¨urttemberg, in , he was always a precocious stu- dent; at the age of fifteen he was admitted to the Protestant Seminary at T¨ubingen, where he shared a roomwith two other students who were to become close friends, G. W. F. Hegel and Friedrich H¨olderlin. (Both H¨olderlin and Hegel were five years older than Schelling.) He published his first major philosophical work at the age of nineteen and, by the time he was twenty-nine, he had published more philosophy books than most people could even transcribe in a lifetime. By (at the age of twenty-three), Schelling became an “extraordinary” professor at Jena and Fichte’s successor. Each year, with each new publication, Schelling’s system seemed to change, leading Hegel later sarcastically to remark in his Berlin lectures that Schelling had conducted his philosophical edu- cation in public. Josiah Royce quipped that Schelling was the “prince ofthe romantics.” Both Hegel and Royce were right; Schelling was ambi- tious and experimental in temperament, sometimes a bit reckless in his arguments, and he was continually refining and testing out new ideas and ever open to revising old ones. As one ofthe standard works on Schelling’s thought puts it, Schelling’s process was always “becoming,” never finished. Hence, any presentation of “Schelling’s philosophy” can only be either a presentation of some time-slice of it or else display the developmental history of a train of thought that was cut short only by Schelling’s death. Nonetheless, Schelling’s whole early evolving corpus until was in some basic ways based on a dominant leitmotif that was already apparent in a letter he wrote to Hegel in February, ,inwhichhe Xavier Tilliette, Schelling: Une Philosophie en Devenir (Paris: Vrin, ). –: Schelling proudly declared to his friend that: “In the meantime I have become a Spinozist!” and explained that as he understood things (under the influence of Fichte), the only real difference between idealist Kantian systems and “dogmatic” systems had to do with their respective starting points: “That the former takes as its starting-point the absolute I (not yet conditioned by any object), the latter the absolute object or Not-I,” whereas the truth ofthe matter has to lie in some way of reconciling those two starting-points with each other that is nonetheless consistent with human spontaneity and autonomy championed by Kant. Schelling thus accepted Fichte’s way of putting the issue, but he did not think, at least at first, that the choice of starting points was simply a matter of one’s char- acter, nor did he think that the two starting points formed an either/or choice; both needed to be understood as different manifestations of some one underlying “absolute” reality as Spinoza had thought. Moreover, this renewed Spinozismhad to be such so as to answer Jacobi’s doubts and to secure the reality of human freedom; as Schelling rather exuberantly put it in his monograph, Ofthe I as the Principle of Philosophy or On the Unconditional in Human Knowledge: “The beginning and end of all philos- ophy is freedom!” Schelling quickly absorbed Fichte’s reworking of Kant, and he seems to have immediately accepted the distinction Reinhold and Fichte pop- ularized between the “spirit” and the “letter” of Kantian philosophy. As he repeatedly stressed in his early writings, he was simply not inter- ested in constructing exegeses of Kantian texts; his concerns were with getting the arguments right for the Kantian conclusions (a sentiment still widespread among interpreters ofKant today). Schelling was quite ab- sorbed by the three dominant issues in the confrontation with Kantian thought during that time: Aenesidemus had put the issue of Kant’s al- leged refutation of skepticism(that is, of Hume) front and center; both Fichte and Aenesidemus had thrown into question the issue of things-in- themselves; and the answer to the questions about the status of freedom in a disenchanted natural world was considered to be still outstanding. The issue of things-in-themselves was particularly vexing and was seen as key to the whole issue; Salomon Maimon, an early exegete and critic G. W. F. Hegel, Briefe von und an Hegel (ed. Johannes Hoffmeister) (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, ), vol. ,no.. F. W. J. Schelling, “Of the I as Principle of Philosophy,” Ofthe I as the Principle of Philosophy or On the Unconditional in Human Knowledge, in F. W. J. Schelling, The Unconditional in Human Knowledge: Four Early Essays (–) (trans. Fritz Marti) (Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, ), p. ; Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie oder ¨uber das Unbedingte im menschlichen Wissen, in F. W. J. Schelling, Ausgew¨ahlte Schriften (ed. Manfred Frank) (Frankfurt amMain: Suhrkamp, ), , p. . Part II The revolution continued: post-Kantians of Kant’s critical philosophy had accused Kantof violating his own prin- ciples in saying that things-in-themselves cause our sensations of them, since causality on Kant’s view was a category restricted to appearances and not applicable to things-in-themselves. Schelling saw, however, that Fichte had implicitly carried this criticism one step further; what was confusing in Kant’s own view was not simply the application of a cate- gory of appearance to things-in-themselves – it was the ambiguity in the way one spoke ofthe “ground” of appearances in things-in-themselves. “Ground” (Grund, in the German) could mean that things-in-themselves caused our sensations of them; or it could mean that it was the source of whatever reason-giving force those sensations had. As Schelling under- stood Fichte to have argued, causes cannot be reasons, and thus, even if it were true that things-in-themselves caused our sensations, those causes could never offer us reasons for belief. Causality involved facts; judgments involved norms. However, Fichtean idealism had trouble making sense ofthe relation between experience as ground of belief and experience as caused by the world, since it viewed everything as a posit by the “I”; even the “Not-I” was itself something posited by the “I.” In “Of the I as Principle of Philosophy” – an essay published in (when he was twenty) – Schelling posed the issue quite starkly as that between either knowledge as a systemof self-enclosed beliefs and reasons having no contact with the world; or as some form of “foundationalism” (as Reinhold had thought). If the only reasons for beliefs are other beliefs and not causes, then the most we can have is “an eternal cycle of proposi- tions, each continually and reciprocally flowing into the other, a chaos in which no element can diverge from another,” in short, only a “spinning” (a Kreislauf ) ofthe conceptual web internal to itself having “no reality.” This seems to imply some form of “foundationalism,” one’s having to know something basic without having to know anything else. How- ever, for such a “foundation” to work, it has to be self-certifying, which (as Fichte had argued) only leads to some form of “intellectual intuition,” which, if ofthe truth, must be an intuition of an identity of thought and being. Schelling’s key idea was to combine his newly found Spinozism with a rejection of what he took to be Fichte’s key error. Fichte had argued that the basic distinction between the subjective and the objective had itself to be either a subjective or objective distinction; and that, since ranking Schelling, “Of the I,” p. ; Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie,p.. As Schelling puts it: “If there is any genuine knowledge at all, there must be knowledge which I do not reach by way of some other knowledge, but through which alone all other knowledge is possible,”Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie,p.; “Of the I,” p. . –: Schelling it to be an objective distinction would only result in yet another formof discredited dogmatism (in a conflation of reasons and causes), the distinc- tion itself therefore had to be a subjective distinction, to be a distinction that the “I” itself “posited” between itself and the “Not-I.” In fact, so Schelling was to argue, the distinction between subjective and objective was itself neither subjective nor objective but relative to something else, the “absolute,” and available therefore only to a formof “intuition,” as awayofseeing things in terms of how both subjectivity and objectivity were points of view stemming from something deeper than themselves. Beginning philosophy with the distinction between subjects and objects was already starting too late in the game, and all the problems of post- Kantian philosophy, including Aenesidemus’s skepticism, stemmed from beginning with the subject/object division being taken for granted. Both should be seen instead as viewpoints arising together, co-equally. Following Fichte, the youthful Schelling thought that the unity ofthe subjective and the objective had nonetheless to be an “absolute I,” which he nevertheless interpreted in Spinozistic, non-Fichtean terms as the expression of some underlying “absolute” reality common to both the ordinary (“empirical”) sense ofthe “I” and the natural world (the “Not-I”) that it strives to know and transform. This “absolute I” straddles the boundary between subjective experience and the objective world, and in intuiting the “I” in intellectual intuition, we are intuiting the basis by which the natural world thereby manifests itself to us in our experience and gives us reasons for belief. Only in this way does idealismescape skep- ticism, namely, by doing away with the basic motivation for skepticism in the first place, that picture ofthe world with subjective experiences on the one side of a sharp divide and a realmof objective matters-of-fact on the other side. Moreover, so Schelling concluded early on, since that new picture requires an “intellectual intuition,” a new way of viewing the problem, that aspect of philosophizing in principle cannot be a matter of “argument” but a matter of “seeing,” of adopting a new view of things that in effect dissolves rather than refutes the problem; or, as Schelling expressed it: “Hence this question cannot be dissolved (aufgel¨ost) except in the way in which Alexander dissolved the Gordian knot, that is, by sublating (aufzuheben) the question. Hence it is quite simply unanswer- able, because it can be answered only in such a way that it can never again be raised.” We must shift our pictures of ourselves fromone view to another in an act of intellectual intuition; instead of seeing ourselves Philosophische Briefe ¨uber Dogmatismus und Kritizismus,pp.–,inSchellings Werke (ed. Manfred Schr¨oter) (Munich: C. H. Beck and Oldenburg, ), vol. ; Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,p.. Part II The revolution continued: post-Kantians or our experiences as separated by a boundary line between subjec- tive and objective, we must “intuit” that in drawing such a boundary, we are ourselves already on both sides ofthe dividing line, indeed, draw- ing the boundary ourselves. This emphasis on “intuition” – Anschauung, “viewing,” or “seeing” – remained with Schelling for his whole life; cen- tral to this thought was his conviction that there was no way of ultimately arguing for the basic ways we interpreted the world, since all forms of ar- gument presupposed a basic “take” on the ultimate structure of things which could not be demonstrated within that form of argument itself; instead, at the level of basic ways of comprehending the world, we re- solved basic problems and contradictions by learning to “see” or “view” things – to “intuit” them– in a different way, to adopt a different basic “picture” of things. The “intellectual intuition” ofthe “absolute” is thus a view of our subjective lives as united with the course of nature in such a way that Aenesidemus’ style of skepticismsimply can no longer take hold of us – not because we have been argued out of it but because it can no longer have any grip on the kind of person we thereby come to be once we have adopted that new picture of ourselves. Again, as Schelling put it in : “We must be what we wish to call ourselves theoretically. And nothing can convince us of being that, except our very striving to be just that. This striving realizes our knowledge of ourselves, and thus this knowledge becomes the pure product of our freedom. We ourselves must have worked our way up to the point fromwhich we want to start. People cannot get there by arguing themselves up to that point (hinaufvern¨unfteln), nor can they be argued into that point by others.” Moreover, it would seemto follow that this intellectual intuition cannot itself be a piece of conceptual knowledge, since conceptual knowledge has to do with the “subjective” aspect ofthe way in which the world manifests itself; or, as Schelling puts it, “for the absolute cannot be me- diated at all, hence it can never fall into the domain of demonstrable concepts.” To bring it under concepts would mean to bring it into the inferential sphere, which would be to threaten the whole enterprise with just being a “spinning” of concepts with each other and perhaps to have no connection with a reality outside of themselves. For this to work, though, spontaneity had to be somehow at one with receptivity in human knowledge; to be led to the point where conceptual Philosophische Briefe ¨uber Dogmatismus und Kritizismus,p.; Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,p.. Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie,p.; “Of the I,” p. . –: Schelling argument is of no more value, Schelling concluded, is to be led “into a region where I do not find firmground, but must produce it myself in order to stand firmly upon it.” The construction of such “firmground” cannot be given to us but must be freely, spontaneously brought forth by us; yet, at the same time, such spontaneity must not be unhinged from the natural world. As Schelling worked out the implications of this view, he also began to break gradually, then more decisively with his Fichtean beginnings. Fichte, so he concluded, was too subjective in his approach; the “Not-I” was simply a posit that the “I” required for its own self-consciousness. Such a view, while emphasizing the spontaneity ofthe “I,” could never do justice to the independent reality ofthe world. By , Schelling had worked out his own stance on these matters. The “intellectual in- tuition” ofthe rational and necessary structure ofthe world required philosophical reflection to go off on two “tracks” which meet only in an “intuition,” an insight or “view” ofthe whole. That insight had to bring together two different viewpoints, each of which is necessary for our grasp of our lives as free, autonomous beings in a natural world. One viewpoint understands us as a part of nature; the other understands us as a self-determining being; the two together are, however, only manifes- tations of one underlying reality, the “absolute.” In almost all of his early writings in the s and s, Schelling appealed to Leibniz’s notion of a “pre-established harmony” between mind and nature to make his point, always stressing, though, that he did not think that this harmony could be the result of some kind of external ordering – and thus that the idea that God arranged our representations and things-in-themselves so that they would match was not even to be seriously considered – but had to be the result of some kind of deeper unity, even identity of mind and nature, as Spinoza had thought. Schelling began diagnosing the root of modern skepticism about whether our representations match up with things-in-themselves as re- sulting fromwhat he (and those who followed him) called “reflection” or “reflective philosophy.” “Reflection,” in the sense Schelling intended it, was close in meaning to “analysis.” When we reflect on something – for example, on the conditions under which we can know something about a Philosophische Briefe ¨uber Dogmatismus und Kritizismus,p.; Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism,p.. The best overall presentation and defense of Schelling’s thought in English is Andrew Bowie, Schelling and Modern European Philosophy: An Introduction (London: Routledge, ); Bowie’s work draws on the pathbreaking work done by Manfred Frank; in particular, see Frank, Eine Einf¨uhrung in Schellings Philosophie. Part II The revolution continued: post-Kantians world independent of us – we necessarily break apart items that are orig- inally at one with each other, and we arrange those items in some kind of order. Thus, we separate “representations” fromthe objects that they seemto represent, and we then wonder how it is that they are supposed to be brought back together. What such “reflective” modes of thought necessarily fail to grasp (because they are reflective) is that, unless there were already a pre-reflective unity of thought and being, reflection could not do its work, that without our already “being in touch ” with things , we could not begin to reflect on the conditions for our making true asser- tions. However, this original unity, as pre-reflective, cannot thereby itself be reflectively established; it can only be apprehended in an “intellectual intuition.” Naturphilosophie In , Schelling published his Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature, and the success of that book made what he took to calling Naturphilosophie,for better or worse, one ofthe major areas in German philosophy for the first half ofthe nineteenth century. Naturphilosophie was not philosophy of science, and it was also not quite the same as a “philosophy of na- ture”; rather, it was to be an a priori study ofthe “Idea” of nature. At first, Schelling conceived of it as drawing on the findings of empirical science to give us an understanding of how the results of empirical nat- ural science were in fact compatible and at one with our own subjective, more poetic, appreciation of nature – our intimations, for example, that some ways of life went “against” our nature or that some ways of living were more “in tune” with our natural proclivities than were others, even though the Newtonian conception of nature had no roomwithin it for such intimations. Nonetheless, although it was to be linked to empiri- cal scientific research, such a Naturphilosophie, in Schelling’s mind, had nothing to do with either applying abstract philosophical principles to scientific practice or results – nothing, Schelling said, could be “a more pitiful, workaday occupation” than such an endeavor – and it also had to follow the “basic rule of admitting absolutely no hidden elemental In the System of Transcendental Idealism, Schelling makes the point that since consciousness presupposes the basic distinction in all intentionality between thought and object, sensing and sensed, “a philosophy which starts fromconsciousness will therefore never be able to explain this conformity [of thought and object], nor is it explicable at all without an original identity, whose principle necessarily lies beyond consciousness,” F. W. J. Schelling, System of Transcendental Idealism (trans. Peter Heath) (Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, ), p. (); Ausgew¨ahlte Schriften,p.. –: Schelling substances in bodies, the reality of which can in no way be established by experience.” As Schelling thus originally conceived of it, Naturphilosophie was to construct the a priori view of nature that empirical investigations in fact presupposed in their experimental procedures; as he worked it out, however, it came more and more to signify a specific – many would say idiosyncratic – approach to philosophy. (It is therefore best simply to leave the term, Naturphilosophie, in the original German than to suggest that it was only a distinct field of philosophy, “philosophy of nature.”) The rise of natural science had originally seemed to split philosophy into the dueling camps of rationalists and empiricists; the motive for each camp had been the necessity to account for the way in which the findings of natural science seemed at first blush to contradict the basic elements ofthe human experience ofthe world – rationalists explained this by arguing that the mind could apprehend the secrets of nature independently of experience through, for example, mathematical inves- tigation, and the empiricists argued that the findings of natural science were no more than methodologically purified extrapolations from our own experience. Schelling concluded that, since Kant had finally put an end to the endless seesaw between the two camps, and since Fichte had drawn out the proper implications ofthe Kantian view, it was now time to show that the new dueling camps of modern philosophy – “realism” and “idealism” – were themselves only manifestations of some deeper underlying worldview that was the unity ofthe two, and the vehicle to do that would be the dual development of transcendental philosophy and Naturphilosophie united in a doctrine ofthe “intellectual intuition” ofthe absolute. Moreover, Naturphilosophie had to show how freedomwas compatible with nature without having to invoke any kind of suspension of natural law or noumenal realm where such laws did not hold sway. That meant, Schelling concluded, that the mechanistic view of nature could not be correct. As he put it: “Suppose I am myself a mere piece of mecha- nism. But what is caught up in mere mechanism cannot step out ofthe mechanism and ask: How has all this become possible?” In drawing out his own answer to that question, Schelling took his own inspira- tion not so much from Fichte, Spinoza, or Leibniz but from Kant. In the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, Kant had criticized what he took to be the Newtonian conception of motion because ofthe way he took it F. W. J. Schelling, Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature (trans. Errol E. Harris and Peter Heath) (Cambridge University Press, ), pp. –. Ibid., p. . Part II The revolution continued: post-Kantians to rest on suppositions about absolute space that were ruled out by Kant’s own systemof transcendental idealism. Kant was therefore led to see Newton’s absolute space instead as an “Idea” of reason, a conception of an ideal end-point toward which the kinds of judgments that one makes on the basis of a Newtonian systemtend to converge. (That ideal end- point would be the center of mass ofthe entire universe, something that could never be given in experience. ) However, if the concept of absolute space could not be assumed and could only function instead as a regula- tive ideal in terms of which we investigated nature, then, so Kant argued, we could not go on to do as Newton had done, namely, to use absolute space as the basis for defining the laws of “true” motion (as opposed to “relative” or merely apparent motions, such as the sun “appearing” to move while the earth “appears” to be at rest). Therefore, for Newtonian investigations to be possible in the first place, we must have a method for distinguishing true fromapparent motion, which required investigations that rested on a priori presuppositions about the nature of what was movable – which, for Kant, was equivalent to determining the a priori determinations ofthe empirically constituted conception of matter. This, in turn, led Kant to hold that there must a priori be two different forces at work in matter, those of attraction and repulsion. Attraction is necessary because, in presupposing a center of mass, we need a concept of univer- sal gravitation, of matter as exhibiting essentially a universal attraction for all other matter; in doing that, however, we must also presuppose a countervailing force of repulsion, since if there were only attraction, all matter would condense to one point (just as, if there were only re- pulsion, all matter would scatter into virtual nothingness). Mechanics, Kant concluded, rests on a priori determinations more properly set by transcendental philosophy. Absolute space, like the idea of a common center of mass, is thus, for Kant, an Idea of reason. For Schelling, though, if nature is purely a mechanical system (as Kant argued in his first Critique), and if one eschews appeal to things- in-themselves (and therefore eschews any notion of transcendental causality), and if we are necessarily to construe ourselves as free, natural Immanuel Kant, Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (trans. James W. Ellington) (Indiana- polis: Hackett Publishing Company, ). See Michael Friedman, Kant and the Exact Sciences. Friedman notes: “Newton presents the laws of motion as facts, as it were, about a notion of true motion that is antecedently well defined .For Kant, on the other hand, since there is no such antecedently well-defined notion of true motion, the laws of motions are not facts but rather conditions under which alone the notion of true motion first has objective meaning,” p. . My own understanding of these issues has drawn heavily on Michael Friedman’s discussion in Kant and the Exact Sciences,ch., “Metaphysical Foundations of Newtonian Science.” –: Schelling beings, then we are left with an insoluble contradiction unless we hold that nature, regarded as a whole, as “Idea,” is not a mechanical system but a series of basic “forces” or “impulses” that mirror at the basic level the same kind of determinations that are operative in us at the level of self-conscious freedom. The a priori study ofthe basic forces at work in nature – Naturphilosophie itself – must construct an account of nature that is continuous with our freedom; it must “re-enchant” nature so that we once more have a place in it. The re-enchantment of nature would have to consist in understand- ing nature as a whole in organic and not in purely mechanical terms; indeed, Kant’s own notion of reflective, teleological judgments pointed to that very solution. We must think of organisms as having their pur- posiveness within themselves, as being what Kant called in a footnote an “organization,” where “each member of such a whole should in- deed be not merely a means, but also an end.” Organisms are such “wholes”; moreover, it does no good to suppose that they are the results of some external hand (such as God) organizing them, since that would merely bestow an external, instead of an internal purpose on them, and it does equally no good to postulate some special “life force” (in any event, a “completely self-contradictory concept,” as Schelling put it). Purposiveness, which is necessary in thinking of organisms, exists only for a judging intellect; and, since this intellect cannot be outside ofthe organism, it must be somehow immanent within it. “Intellect,” that is, must somehow already be at work in nature, even if only in a sub- merged form, and nature as a whole, considered philosophically, must be viewed as a formof “organization” in the Kantian sense. Nature exhibits Kant’s sense of “purposiveness without a purpose” in that its basic tendencies (like attraction and repulsion) tend toward a growing kind of unity and inwardness that culminates in human communities – Schelling uses the term, Geist, mind or “spirit” in its communal sense – coming to self-consciousness, to an intellectual intuition of itself. Matter gradually organizes itself (quite blindly) into various wholes (having to Kant, Critique of Judgment, § . The whole citation, which is crucial for understanding Schelling’s notion of “organization” goes as the following: “On the other hand, the analogy of these direct natural purposes can serve to elucidate a certain association [among people], though one found more often as an idea than in actuality: in speaking ofthe complete transformation of a large people into a state, which took place recently, the word organization was frequently and very aptly applied to the establishment of legal authorities, etc. and even to the entire body politic. For each member in such a whole should indeed be not merely a means but also an end; and while each member contributes to making the whole possible, the Idea of that whole should in turn determine the member’s position and function.” Schelling, Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature,p.. [...]... distinction led Schelling to redescribe the Kantian conception ofthe unknowable thing-in-itself as only the hypostatization of our own ideal, norm-constituting activity See System of Transcendental Idealism, p (); Ausgew¨ hlte Schriften, p Schelling also redescribes the other Kantian a conceptions ofthe ideality of space and time, of substance as persistence over time, ofthe schematism of judgments,... which is “neither nature nor freedom and yet is linked with the basis of freedom, the supersensible.” Schelling took that one step further: the “absolute” which is the unity and basis ofthe distinction between subjective and objective points of view is also that which is the unity of both nature and freedom while being neither of them; consequently, the absolute (what Kant had called the “indeterminate... his full reevaluation ofthe relative priorities of Naturphilosophie and Kantian-inspired transcendental philosophy The System of Transcendental Idealism was Schelling s bold attempt to offer a synthetic account of what Kant s three Critiques would be like if they were rewritten as one work revised in light of his own and Fichte’s continuation ofthe Kantian project Although Schelling conceded, as... ourselves and to the world in general, it is the poet and the painter as the better artificers of such “vision” who best grasp the “absolute identity” of mind and nature, not the natural scientist, bound as he is to discursive forms If anything, it is the aesthetic intuition ofthe whole of reality, the “identity” of mind and nature, that orients and constrains what would otherwise be the unconstrained... by others; he must begin, that is, first with others legislating for him and only gradually grow into the role of autonomous co-legislator Schelling s strategy was thus to fundamentally redescribe Kant s and Fichte’s notions of autonomy in terms of a much more “developmental” model of agency: we become autonomous by moving ourselves (and being moved by others) out ofthe realm of “nature” – out of the. .. is the source of all law As it manifests itself in embodied “free choice,” the “absolute will” can only appear as the pursuit of self-interest on the part of many agents Because of the tensions engendered by that, human sociality produces a “second nature,” the rule of law, not as a moral demand, but as a kind of Hobbesian hedge against the destructiveness of unbridled selfinterest (Indeed, so Schelling. .. sensation, only the limit was disclosed; here, something beyond the limit, whereby the I explains the limit to itself.” This is the notion of the thing-in-itself System of Transcendental Idealism, p () Ibid., p () Part II The revolution continued: post-Kantians metaphysically fixed but normatively determined, and the “intuition” of where that boundary lies itself always “oversteps the boundary,... representaa tion the I merely takes in, and is pure receptivity, he cannot maintain, owing to the spontaneity involved therein, and indeed because even in the things themselves (as represented), there emerges the unmistakable trace of an activity of the self The influence in question will therefore originate, not from things as we present them to ourselves, but from things as they are independently of the representations... one with either of these Within human agency, the “dark” principle can be “torn apart” from the principle of “light,” and thus arises the possibility of evil The principles of “light” and “darkness” do not represent two entities or even two different and opposing forces The principle of “light” (reason, order, intelligibility) instead grows out of the principle of “dark” (chaos, unreason, the unintelligible),... effectuates itself in the denial ofthe possibility of love and thus ofthe full reality of others The ability to ward off evil thus must come not from any act of will, since that would be impossible, but from an openness to the divine, and the degree of one’s openness is itself not entirely up to one’s individual will but has something to do with the “self ” with which one is born Evil, as Schelling puts . ambiguity in the way one spoke of the “ground” of appearances in things-in-themselves. “Ground” (Grund, in the German) could mean that things-in-themselves. step further; what was confusing in Kant s own view was not simply the application of a cate- gory of appearance to things-in-themselves – it was the ambiguity