Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống
1
/ 28 trang
THÔNG TIN TÀI LIỆU
Thông tin cơ bản
Định dạng
Số trang
28
Dung lượng
179,66 KB
Nội dung
5 Sensationandappearance In the preceding two chapters, we have had a good deal to say about various kinds of mental state. Although we have focused chiefly on propositional attitude states, such as beliefs, we have also had occasion to mention sensational states, such as pain and nausea. States of the latter sort lack ‘proposi- tional content’. When one feels a pain, one may feel it ‘in’ a certain part of one’s body, such as one’s left big toe, and consequently have a belief that one’s left big toe is hurting. But we must distinguish that belief – which does of course have propositional content – from the pain which gives rise to it, which does not. We do, it is true, say such things as ‘I feel that my left big toe is hurting’, but such a statement is more like the expression of a perceptual judgement than a report that one is experiencing a certain kind of sensation. In the latter kind of report, a term denoting a kind of sensa- tion figures as the direct grammatical object of a verb such as ‘feel’, as in ‘I feel a pain in my left big toe’. An example of a sentence clearly expressing a perceptual judgement would be ‘I see that the tree is in front of the house’, in which the verb takes a that-clause as its object. Now, perceptual states, such as an experience of seeing a tree to be in front of a house, are curious in that they seem partly like propositional attitude states and partly like sensational states. They are like the latter inasmuch as they involve qual- itative characteristics – the notorious ‘qualia’ of experience discussed in chapter 3 – but they are like the former in having some sort of conceptual content. It may be that some- one – a young infant, for example – can see a tree to be in 102 Sensationandappearance 103 front of a house without possessing the concepts of a tree or a house, but it does seem that one must be able to bring the objects in question under concepts of some sort if one is to have such a perceptual experience, since such an experience seems to involve a recognition of those objects as objects of certain kinds. We shall have to postpone consideration of some of the complex issues involved here until the next chap- ter, however, when we shall discuss theories of perception in more depth. What we are going to concentrate on in the current chap- ter are those qualitative features of experience which seem to be present both in purely sensational states, such as pains, and in perceptual states, such as visual experiences. One of the things that we shall need to do is to see what motivates our talk of experiences having such qualitative features. Another will be to examine the ontological implications of such talk: should we or should we not reify the ‘qualia’ of experience, by regarding them as ‘inner’ objects of experien- tial awareness, in the way that so-called ‘sense-datum’ theor- ists do? Finally, we shall need to examine what implications these qualitative features of experience have for our concep- tion of the properties that we ascribe to the ‘external’ objects of perception – things such as trees and houses. For many of those properties, such as colour-properties, may seem to have more to do with how we experience the objects in question than they do with how those objects are in themselves. APPEARANCEAND REALITY It is a commonplace that things are not always really as they seem to be: appearances can deceive. There is a danger, how- ever, of magnifying this truism into a doctrine of cosmic sig- nificance by talking of ‘Appearance’ and ‘Reality’ as if they were realms separated by an impassable gulf. Sceptics over the ages have always tempted us to do this. A more sober, if less exciting, view to take is that talk about how things appear to be is an integral part of talk about how things really are. It is just as much an objective fact about a coin An introduction to the philosophy of mind104 that it ‘appears’ elliptical when seen at an oblique angle as that it is ‘really’ round in shape. It is true that we commonly judge a thing’s overall shape by observing how it appears from different directions, and that sometimes such a judge- ment can be mistaken. But we should be wary of concluding from this and similar examples that we can only ever observe the ‘appearances’ of things and are compelled to rely on doubtful inferences from these in order to judge what their ‘real’ properties are. The questionable step here is the reifica- tion of ‘appearances’ – the supposition that ‘appearances’ are themselves objects of observation and, indeed, the ‘immedi- ate’ objects of observation from which our knowledge of so- called ‘external’ objects, such as coins, must be inferred. In ordinary speech, it is harmless enough to paraphrase the sen- tence ‘The coin appears elliptical’ by means of the sentence ‘The appearance of the coin is elliptical’. Harm is threatened only when a philosopher unwarrantedly assumes that the latter sentence implies that there is something – the ‘appear- ance of the coin’ – that is elliptical. What is called for at this point is closer attention to how we use the verb ‘appear’ and certain closely related verbs, such as ‘look’ and ‘feel’. It would seem that these verbs have at least two distinct kinds of use, an epistemic use and a phe- nomenal use. 1 Consider first the following case. I am at the seaside and spot a distant figure in the water moving his arm about in the air, and I say ‘That swimmer appears to be waving’. What I am doing here is expressing a cautious judge- ment that the swimmer is waving, recognising that I might be mistaken – for perhaps the swimmer is really not waving, but drowning. This is the epistemic use of ‘appear’ – ‘epi- stemic’ because it is used to qualify or hedge an implicit claim to knowledge made by the speaker. But now compare this case with the example of the coin discussed earlier, 1 For more on the uses of ‘look’ or ‘appear’, see Frank Jackson, Perception: A Repres- entative Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), ch. 2. See also my Subjects of Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 97– 100, 110–12. Sensationandappearance 105 where the speaker says ‘The coin appears elliptical from this angle’. Here the speaker is clearly not expressing a cautious judgement that the coin is elliptical (much less that it is elliptical ‘from this angle’, which scarcely makes any sense). So what is the speaker trying to express in such a case? Before we venture to answer this question, let us consider a few more examples of the same sort. When viewing a red ball under a blue light, one may say ‘The ball looks black in this light’. When dipping one’s cold hand into a basin of luke- warm water, one may say ‘This water feels hot to my hand’. When drinking a dry wine just after having eaten something very sweet, one may say ‘This wine tastes sour to me’. In each case, it seems, one is trying to express something about what it is like to perceive an object in certain somewhat unusual conditions. In other words, one is trying to convey something about the qualititative or phenomenal character of one’s per- ceptual experience, rather than just something about the object that one is perceiving (the coin, the ball, the water, or the wine). So what, exactly, does a statement such as ‘The coin appears elliptical from this angle’ mean, when ‘appear’ is used in what I shall call the ‘phenomenal’ sense? Perhaps it means something roughly like this: ‘Seeing the coin from this angle is very like seeing an elliptical object face-on’. Here one is comparing one kind of perceptual experience with another in order to draw attention to a qualititative feature which both kinds of experience have in common, and thereby convey to one’s audience some idea of what that qualitative feature is. And notice what kind of perceptual experience one chooses for the sake of comparison here: one chooses an experience which is in some sense ‘standard’, ‘normal’, or ‘optimal’ for the purpose of forming a reliable judgement with regard to the relevant property of the object perceived. Thus, in order to form a reliable judgement concerning the shape of a thin, flat object such as a coin, one does best to look at it face-on. (Here, of course, I am speaking of its ‘shape’ in the two dimensions in which it is spread out thinly; if one wants to see how thin it is, one should look at it An introduction to the philosophy of mind106 edgewise-on.) Similarly, in order to form a reliable judge- ment concerning the surface colour of an object, one does best to look at it in ordinary daylight. Ordinary daylight con- stitutes ‘standard’ or ‘normal’ conditions for viewing the sur- face colours of objects. 2 Generalising, then, perhaps we can say that a sentence of the form ‘Object O appears F in condi- tions C’ – where ‘appear’ has its phenomenal sense – means something like this: ‘Perceiving object O in conditions C is very like perceiving an object which is F in normal conditions for perceiving objects which are F’. If the purpose of the phenomenal use of ‘appear’ is to convey something about the qualitative features of our experiences, why do we have recourse to such a roundabout procedure? Why don’t we simply describe those features ‘dir- ectly’? But how could we have generated the necessary vocabulary? It is no accident that ordinary language contains few resources for directly describing the qualitative features of our experiences. As children we necessarily learn, first of all, words to describe objects that we and other speakers of our language can perceive in common – objects such as coins, balls, and basins of water. As part of this process, we learn under what conditions we are best situated to form reliable judgements, based on observation, as to what properties those objects possess, and thus how best to describe them. It is a relatively sophisticated intellectual achievement to real- ise that, in being perceivers of objects, we are also subjects of perceptual experience, and that our perceptual experi- ences are themselves capable of description in various ways. But we need not (and possibly could not) learn a wholly new vocabulary in order to describe those experiences. Instead, we can simply exploit the descriptive vocabulary which we have already learnt to apply to the familiar objects of percep- tion, with the aid of verbs like ‘appear’ and ‘look’ used in the phenomenal sense. But, of course, this procedure harbours 2 A word of caution is in place here, as the notion of ‘standard’ or ‘normal’ condi- tions has been challenged by some philosophers: see, for example, C. L. Hardin, Color for Philosophers (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988), pp. 67ff. Sensationandappearance 107 snares for unwary philosophers. For we may be tempted to suppose that the descriptive vocabulary which we originally learnt to apply to the familiar, ‘external’ objects of percep- tion quite literally also applies – or perhaps really only applies – to qualititative features of our experiences. Thus, we may be tempted to suppose that qualitative features of our experiences may themselves be ‘elliptical’ or ‘black’ or ‘hot’ or ‘sour’, when, perhaps, these adjectives are properly only applicable to the familiar objects that we perceive rather than to our perceptual experiences of them. Where the truth lies in this difficult matter is something we shall look into later in this chapter. SENSE-DATUM THEORIES AND THE ARGUMENT FROM ILLUSION I have already spoken of the dangers of reifying appearances and of supposing that familiar descriptive terms, such as ‘elliptical’ and ‘black’, apply quite literally to the qualitative features of our perceptual experiences. But some philo- sophers have effectively combined these two contentious lines of thought by treating the ‘qualia’ of experience as ‘inner’ objects of awareness in their own right, describable as really possessing the properties which ‘external’ objects appear to possess. Historically, one argument above all others has been invoked in support of this doctrine: the notorious argument from illusion. 3 The argument proceeds in four stages. (1) First, it is noted that in certain circumstances an object can appear other than the way it really is. To use again our well-worn example, a round coin appears elliptical when it is seen at an oblique angle. (2) Next, it is contended that in these cir- cumstances we are aware of something that really does have the property which the object in question merely appears to have: thus, for example, it is contended that we are aware of something that really is elliptical. (3) Then it is pointed out 3 For a particularly well-known presentation of the argument from illusion, see A. J. Ayer, The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge (London: Macmillan, 1940), ch. 1. An introduction to the philosophy of mind108 that this ‘something’ cannot be identical with the object which merely appears to have the property in question, because these things have different properties. Thus, the elliptical object of awareness cannot be the coin, since the latter is round rather than elliptical. (4) Finally, it is urged that even in circumstances in which an ‘external’ object appears no different from the way it really is – for instance, when a round coin is seen face-on and thus appears round – there is still an ‘inner’ object of awareness, distinct from that ‘external’ object, which possesses the property in question (in this case, roundness). The reasoning behind this last stage of the argument is that there is no relevant difference between this special case and other cases which differ from it only marginally. Thus, it is urged, if the existence of an inner object of awareness must be acknowledged in the coin case for all angles of observation under which the coin appears elliptical, no matter how slightly so, it would be extravagant to suppose that such an inner object does not also exist in the limiting case when the coin appears round, since this case is continuous with the previous ones. These supposed inner objects of awareness have been variously dubbed, but are most commonly called ‘sense-data’ or ‘sensa’ (the singular forms of these nouns being ‘sense-datum’ and ‘sensum’). 4 It seems fairly clear that the argument from illusion, conceived as above as an argument for the existence of sense-data, is implicitly question-begging – that is, it assumes, at least in part, what it is supposed to prove. What it is supposed to prove is that, whenever we perceive an ‘external’ object (if, indeed, we ever do), what we are ‘directly’ aware of is some ‘inner’ object, which really pos- sesses the properties which that external object appears to possess. However, in stage (2) of the argument it is simply asserted, without proof, that in certain circumstances we 4 For a sophisticated modern defence of the sense-datum theory, see Jackson, Per- ception: A Representative Theory, ch. 4. At one time, I favoured the theory myself: see my ‘Indirect Perception and Sense Data’, Philosophical Quarterly 31 (1981), pp. 330–42. More recently, sense-data have been vigorously championed by Howard Robinson, in his Perception (London: Routledge, 1994). Sensationandappearance 109 are aware of something which really does possess a property which some external object merely appears to possess. Why should we accept that? It must be conceded that in some cases, at least, the impulse to believe something like this is very strong. Try, for example, the following experiment. Focus your eyes on some distant object, such as a clock on the other side of the room, and hold your index finger up a few inches in front of your nose. You will seem to see two semi-transparent fingers a little way apart from each other, one to either side of the distant object. It is difficult to resist the temptation to say that in these circumstances you see two elongated, semi-transparent objects of some sort. If that is correct, then at least one of these objects cannot be your finger, since two different things cannot both be identical with one thing. Moreover, since the two objects are very similar to one another, it would seem to be unjus- tifiable to identify one rather than the other of them with your finger, so we should apparently conclude that neither of them is your finger and thus that what you are directly aware of is not your finger but two ‘inner’ objects or sense- data. One possible response to this line of reasoning is to say that it involves a confusion between the number of objects seen and the number of acts of seeing performed. Thus, it may be said, you really see only one elongated, fingerlike object in the circumstances described – namely, your finger – but you see it twice, once with each eye. As seen with one eye, the finger appears slightly displaced to the left, while as seen with the other eye, it appears slightly displaced to the right. However, the sense-datum theorist can accept the latter description of the situation as correct, as far as it goes, without conceding that he is making a mistake in claiming that two distinct ‘inner’ objects of awareness are present in these circumstances. Indeed, he will no doubt urge that he is in a position to explain why the finger appears to be in two different places at once, namely, because two spatially separated ‘appear- ances’ or sense-data of the finger are present. From this example, I think it is clear that the dispute between sense- An introduction to the philosophy of mind110 datum theorists and their opponents is not one which is going to be resolved by any sort of simple knock-down argument. OTHER ARGUMENTS FOR SENSE-DATA Besides appealing to illusions, sense-datum theorists also appeal to other evidence in support of their position. Thus they also appeal to the existence of hallucinations. Illusions and hallucinations differ in the following way. In the case of an illusion, one perceives a certain ‘external’ object but it appears, in some respect, other than the way it really is – for instance, one sees one’s finger, but it appears to be in two different places at once. In the case of an hallucination, however, one does not perceive any ‘external’ object at all, of the sort that one seems to perceive. For example – perhaps under the influence of some drug – one may seem to see a snake wriggling across the floor, when in fact there is nothing but a plain carpet on the floor. Here the sense-datum theorist will urge that, in this par- ticular case, one really is aware of some snakelike object, which evidently cannot be identical with any external object which one sees, since no appropriate external object is present – not even something which might appear snakelike, such as a stick which happens to be lying on the carpet. Then the theorist will go on to urge that, since this hallucinatory experience of seeming to see a snake is so like an experience of seeing a real snake, it is reason- able to suppose that even in the latter case what one is directly aware of is some ‘inner’ snakelike object, since this is all that one can be directly aware of in the hallucinatory case. But, as with the argument from illusion, opponents of the sense-datum theory may simply refuse to accept the sense-datum theorist’s crucial claim that, in the hallucinat- ory case, one is at least aware of some snakelike object. They may insist that the most that can safely be said about the hallucinatory case is that in it one seems to see some snakelike object – and seeming to see a snakelike Sensationandappearance 111 object cannot necessarily be equated with seeing (or being aware of) a seemingly snakelike object. However, this is not the only possible response which opponents of the sense-datum theory may make to the argu- ment from hallucination. Some of them challenge the sense- datum theorist’s claim that having a hallucinatory experi- ence can be exactly like having a veridical perceptual experience – that, to use our example, having a hallucination of a snake wriggling across the floor can be exactly like actu- ally seeing a snake wriggling across the floor. Others challenge the sense-datum theorist’s argument at the point at which it is urged that, since (allegedly) a hallucinatory experience can be exactly like a veridical perceptual experience and in the case of the former one is (allegedly) aware of some ‘inner’ object, it is reasonable to suppose that in the case of a veri- dical perceptual experience, too, what one is directly aware of is some ‘inner’ object or sense-datum. I shall consider this last sort of challenge more fully in the next chapter, in the course of discussing objections to causal theories of percep- tion. Talk of causal theories of perception prompts me to men- tion, if only briefly, one other kind of consideration which sense-datum theorists have often adduced in support of their position. This is the fact that there is always a delay – some- times a very long one – between our perceiving some event and the event itself. Thus, if one is watching a man ham- mering a stake into the ground several hundred yards away, one will hear each strike of the hammer a fraction of a second after one sees it, simply because sound travels much more slowly than light. But even light travels at a finite velocity, so that an astronomer observing a distant supernova today may be seeing a star which, by the time he sees it, no longer exists. Sense-datum theorists are apt to urge at this point that what the astronomer is directly aware of in this case cannot be the star itself, since that no longer exists, and con- sequently that the astronomer must be directly aware of some ‘inner’ object or sense-datum. But opponents of the sense-datum theory can respond simply by challenging the [...]... things in normal viewing conditions And 10 For further interesting discussion of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities and dispositional analyses of colour-predicates, see Colin McGinn, The Subjective View: Secondary Qualities and Indexical Thoughts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), ch 8, and Christopher Peacocke, Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and their Relations (Oxford: Clarendon... satisfactory para- Sensationandappearance 119 phrases of certain complex sense-datum sentences.7 Consider, for instance, a sense-datum report such as ‘I am aware of a red square sense-datum to the right of a blue round sense-datum’ How could one hope to paraphrase this in an adverbial way? It plainly will not do to paraphrase it as ‘I am appeared to redly and squarely and bluely and roundly’, not... Clarendon Press, 1975), Book II, ch 8 For further discussion of Locke’s views about this distinction and more generally about perception, see my Locke on Human Understanding (London: Routledge, 1995), ch 3 Sensation andappearance 121 shape of an object even when viewing it at a reasonable distance and in good light But in the latter sort of case we can resort to procedures of measurement which will... suggesting every ordinary speaker of English explicitly understands ‘is silvery’ to have this meaning Rather, he is advancing this thesis as a philosophical analysis of the concept of being silvery, and hence as revealing the implicit meaning of the predicate in the light of a reflective understanding of our use of it Indeed, the Sensationandappearance 125 sense-datum theorist may urge that the error... posthumously published lectures, Sense and Sensibilia, ed G J Warnock (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962), which are especially critical of Ayer’s account in The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge For more recent criticism, see David M Armstrong, ‘Perception, Sense Data and Causality’, in G F Macdonald (ed.), Perception and Identity (London: Macmillan, 1979) Sensation andappearance 113 worthiness of our perceptual... of account the spatial relation between the two sense-data but also because it fails to preserve the connection between redness and squareness on the one hand and blueness and roundness on the other – that is, it fails to distinguish between the original sense-datum report and the quite different sense-datum report ‘I am aware of a blue square sense-datum to the right of a red round sense-datum’ I shall... other things can stand in genuine relations One immediate advantage of the adverbial theorist’s way of thinking about pains and other bodily sensations is that it helps us to avoid certain awkward questions about where such 116 An introduction to the philosophy of mind sensations are located We speak as if pains were located ‘in’ various parts of our bodies, such as our backs or our toes And yet it is difficult... on Human Understanding, pp 55–8 Sensation andappearance 123 to say that, strictly speaking, the predicate ‘is elliptical’, as applied to an external object such as a coin or a plate, really just means something like ‘is disposed to cause elliptical sense-data in normal viewing conditions’ Then, in the first place, this would undermine his account of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities,... ADVERBIAL THEORY AND SENSE-DATA Having seen how the adverbial theory deals with sensationreports, it is now time to see how it deals with the more difficult case of statements about the qualitative features of perceptual experiences Recall that the sense-datum theorist maintains that, whenever it is true to say that some ‘external’ object appears to have a certain property, Sensationandappearance 117... objects which stand in certain relations to people and possess certain loca6 An important early version of the adverbial theory is to be found in Roderick M Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1957), ch 8 For a more recent account, see Michael Tye, The Metaphysics of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), ch 5 Sensation andappearance 115 . ‘Perception, Sense Data and Causality’, in G. F. Macdonald (ed.), Perception and Identity (London: Macmillan, 1979). Sensation and appearance 113 worthiness. redness and squareness on the one hand and blueness and roundness on the other – that is, it fails to distinguish between the original sense-datum report and