... distinctions.indd 106-107 Should vs Ought to 107 —(only for ought to) do-support vs absence of do-support —(only for ought to) infinitive marker to vs reduced (oughta) vs absent The quantitative... of ought to (cf Kennedy (2002)), which amounts to a should/ ought to ratio of 19:1. Similarly, in Collins’s (2009) study (involving different corpora), the ratio of should to ought to appears to. .. observed from the table that should is much more frequent than ought to in the corpora, with a 9:1 should/ ought to ratio in the spoken corpus and a 36:1 should/ ought to ratio in the written corpus. These
Trang 1should vs Ought to*
Bert Cappelle and Gert De Sutter
University College Ghent / Ghent University
0 Preface
The seeds of this text were sown within Renaat Declerck’s ambitious
but unfinished project on mood and modality. At one project work
meet-ing in 2006, one of us (B.C.) presented some quantitative findmeet-ings about
significant factors in the choice between should and ought to, based on a
fairly restricted data set (150 examples of each modal verb). A mutual
comparison of the contributions of these factors was lacking, and this
pa-per is an attempt to provide this. The idea of using an extensive set of
parameters to investigate the distribution of modal auxiliaries lay at the
heart of the modality project as formulated in its proposal. In this sense,
the present paper is in the spirit of Declerck’s research aims
At the time, however, Declerck did not think that a multifactorial statis-tical analysis of the sort presented here would advance the project.
Instead, he argued that larger sets of examples should instead be examined
with an eye to discovering rare or undescribed usage types. For this
pa-per a set of examples more than three times the original size has been in-vestigated, but our primary aim is not to report special types. Rather, our intention is to show that systematic analysis and coding of what is still a relatively restricted data set (approx 500 authentic examples of each
mod-al verb) can lead to confident conclusions about rarely described or
hither-to undetected usage trends which distinguish these two semantically close
lexical items
1. Should and Ought to: The Challenge
As the following sentences demonstrate, should and ought (to) can be
used as what appear to be stylistic variants of each other (1a, b), as mutual paraphrases to strengthen each other’s meaning (2a, b), and, most remark-ably, in tag questions as proforms for verb phrases containing the other verb, a possibility pointed out by Harris (1986: 353), Palmer (1990: 122), Perkins (1983: 55) and Swan (1995: 496)—though note that, for reasons
that will become clear, a tag with shouldn’t is more frequent than one with oughtn’t (3a, b):
(1) a Tina had no moral sense about this question, no feeling that
children ought to know who their fathers were or should be
fathered by the men their mothers lived with or were married
to. (British National Corpus (henceforth BNC), written dis-course)
b Check the quality of the paper. It should not be limp, shiny
or waxy and the heavily printed areas ought to feel crisp and
slightly rough. (Cobuild corpus, Today Newspaper)
(2) a I’m not all that I should be and all that I ought to be, but by
this time next year I’m going to be a bit better than I am just now, in spiritual terms. (BNC, spoken discourse)
* Many thanks go to Renaat Declerck for allowing the research within his final
proj-ect, on mood and modality, to be conducted from different theoretical and descriptive
angles. This text, as well as the text by Ilse Depraetere in this volume, should prove
that such space for intellectual freedom can bear fruit which we hope will carry
Renaat’s approval. For the implicit views on modality, this text has undoubtedly
bene-fited from the many e-mail exchanges and meetings with Ilse Depraetere, Susan Reed
and An Verhulst which took place within that project. We are also especially grateful
to Marie Baert and Fanny Lauwaers, who coded the corpus examples of should and
ought to in written discourse as part of their course work for the 2006-2007 master’s
course Descriptive English Linguistics: selected Topics at K.U Leuven. Finally, we
would like to thank Naoaki Wada for his helpful suggestions. Any remaining
short-comings are our own
Trang 2b It is all very well setting goals—but what if the very idea
causes psychological reversals, or the athlete’s logical mind
says they ought, should, could do it while their emotional
mind says it doesn’t want to? (Cobuild corpus, UK books)
(3) a. Suppose I ought to tell him that shouldn’t I?
(BNC, spoken discourse)
b And yes, we should be mindful of Muslims’ sensitivities.
But such mindfulness really should run both ways, oughtn’t
it? (http://ace.mu.nu/archives/061590.php) Such examples appear to confirm the received opinion about the modals
should and ought to, namely that they are so similar in meaning that they
can typically substitute for one another. For instance, Palmer (1990: 122)
writes, “It is not at all clear that (…) English makes any distinction
be-tween should and ought to. They seem to be largely interchangeable.”
In Collins’s (2009: 52-53) summary of the literature, similar sentiments
are expressed by Coates (1983: 69), Quirk et al (1985: 227) and
Huddleston and Pullum (2002: 186)
Both should and ought to can also be used as epistemic modals.
Unlike in their deontic use, their function is then not to speak about
obli-gations or to offer advice but rather to express that the fulfilment of a
situ-ation is quite likely or can be reasonably expected given some (perceived)
facts. For example:
(4) a Michael Saunders, UK economist at Salomon Brothers, said
that with output prices already falling sharply, underlying
in-flation should drop below 2.5 per cent by the middle of this
year. (Cobuild corpus, The Times newspaper)
b After all that, some morale-boosting planetary aspects on the
16th, 18th and 22nd ought to make you glow again.
(Cobuild corpus, UK magazines)
In their epistemic use, should and ought to convey a weaker version of
logical necessity as expressed by must. That means that they do not refer
to an inescapable conclusion. Indeed, sometimes they are even used
when the likelihood of a situation is zero (in counterfactual situations);
they then merely express that there was a reasonableness of expectation, which the context makes clear is not borne out, as in the following exam-ples:
(5) a “You stupid fool,” he said aloud. “It should be obvious
what’s happening to the Lands. They’re dying.”
b “Why doesn’t the Thing know where to go?” said Gurder.
“It could find Floridia, so somewhere important like
Blackbury ought to be no trouble.”
(BNC, written discourse)
Clearly, these examples show that should and ought to need not indicate
the speaker’s/writer’s supposition that the statement he makes is true.
Quite often, an epistemic interpretation is mingled with a deontic one.
Consider:
(6) a Unless you are going somewhere subtropical, a wet suit is essential, as is a “foamie”, a fat foam board specially
de-signed for beginners. Any good surfing school should have
plenty of both. (Cobuild corpus, The Times newspaper)
b Who’d like to tell me what twenty-six will be? And then the
next number? Jody. Come on nearly everybody ought to be
able to work this one out now. Eleanor. (…) That’s lovely.
Can you all tell me together what twenty-eight will be?
(BNC, spoken discourse)
In (6a), there is both an epistemic sense (‘go to any good surfing school and you’re likely to find that they have plenty of both’) and a deontic sense (‘any good surfing school owes it to itself to have plenty of both’).
Similarly, in (6b), the modal should in the teacher’s utterance is epistemic
(‘Since all these exercises are similar, I expect that this particular exercise will not pose any difficulty’) but it is undeniably tinged with a deontic reading (‘You’d better be able to work this one out, otherwise it’s clear to
me you haven’t paid any attention’). Note, crucially, that in these
Trang 3in-stances of purely epistemic use or ‘merger,’ should and ought to are again
interchangeable
Given the examples above and the generally accepted view that should
and ought to are semantically equivalent, the challenge is to establish on
which grounds, if any, should and ought to can nonetheless be
distin-guished
2 Differences Proposed in the Literature
We are not the first to rise to the challenge of finding differences
be-tween should and ought to. Some linguists have been dissatisfied with
the generally acknowledged view that these modals are semantically
equivalent and have put forward claims about subtle semantic differences
That there are differences in meaning between should and ought to is
only to be expected. Despite their different ancestry (should originally
being the past tense of shall and ought to the past tense of owe), the close
synonymy of should and ought to goes back to at least Old English (i.e
to before the mid-twelfth century), as appears from attested examples
adopted in the Oxford English Dictionary (Simpson (2000)). The fact
that should and ought to have all this time been allowed to co-exist as
distinct forms occupying the same semantic patch “would seem to justify
the conclusion,” according to Visser (1963: 1637), “that they never had
exactly the same meaning, however closely synonymous they always have
been.”
Yet, exactly what distinguishes these two modals semantically is hard to
pin down. In the following subsections, we will consider three proposals
made in the literature: (i) subjectivity vs objectivity, (ii) absence vs
pres-ence of an implication of non-fulfilment and (iii) relative frequency vs
in-frequency of epistemic reading
In a final subsection, we will consider some other, non-semantic,
differ-ences proposed in the literature
2.1 Subjectivity vs Objectivity
Echoing Swan (1980: 550), Declerck (1991: 377, fn 21) claims:
“Although should and ought to are often interchangeable, there is a slight difference of meaning between them. When using should the speaker ex-presses his own subjective view; ought to is more objective and is used
when the speaker wants to represent something as a law, duty or
regula-tion. For this reason ought to may sound more emphatic than should.”
Declerck offers the following contrast and accompanying comment, again loosely based on Swan (1980: 550):
(7) a You should / ought to congratulate her
b I ought to congratulate her, but I don’t think I will. (should
would sound odd here: it would be strange to give yourself advice and then add that you were not going to follow it.)
(Declerck (1991: 377, fn 21)) Likewise, Collins (2009: 54) makes the claim (though without backing
it up with concrete figures) that while should and ought to are both “more
commonly subjective than objective (…) the proportion of objective cases
is higher with ought to.” He calls a deontic modal “subjective” when it
“indicates what the speaker considers desirable, appropriate or right”
(Collins (2009: 45)) or when “the speaker is giving advice authoritatively
to the addressee” (Collins (2009: 54)) and “objective” when “the appropri-ateness or desirability of the course of action described stands independ-ently of the speaker’s endorsement” (Collins (2009: 45)), i.e., when “gen-erally accepted standards of appropriate behaviour are being invoked”
(Collins (2009: 54)). A very similar distinction can be found in Myhill’s
(1996) study, who argues in detail that should expresses an individual opinion while ought to stresses that an opinion is shared by a group. This
reference to shared opinion, associated with objectivity, can be further
linked to the claim that ought to, more strongly than should, suggests that
the obligation is a duty leading to the greater public good (cf Gailor (1983: 348); Aarts and Wekker (1987: 193))
It is hard to test the impact of subjectivity objectively: in individual ex-amples, it’s not always clear whether the source of modality is grounded
Trang 4in the speaker/writer or in some speaker-external source. We have used a
somewhat different notion of subjectivity in our corpus investigation:
whenever the modality (whether grounded in the speaker/writer or in
some other source) emanates from a personal viewpoint, it is subjective;
when the modal statement is issued without the speaker taking a personal
stance whatsoever, it is objective
One way of testing subjectivity indirectly but fairly reliably might be to
count the number of sentences in a corpus in which should and ought to
occur in a clause which is the complement of an expression of cognition
(assume, believe, feel, reckon, suppose, think, take the view, …). It can
be hypothesised that if should is relatively more subjective and ought to
relatively more objective, sentences like i think you should leave are more
frequent than i think you ought to leave.
2.2. Absence vs. Presence of a Non-fulfilment Implication
Ought to has been claimed to suggest that the actualisation of the
situa-tion referred to “is overdue or may be delayed” (Close (1981: 121)) or
that it might not take place at all (Gailor (1983: 348-349)), implications
which are thought to be absent with should. As Westney (1995: 170)
re-marks, it could also be the reason why As you should know… is less
ag-gressive than As you ought to know … as an opener to give (superfluous)
information or advice, since the latter would impolitely suggest that the
hearer might not yet know
Support for Westney’s observation can be found in the relative
normali-ty of titles of websites or articles starting with “Ten things you ought to
know about…”: here the writer has a good motivation to assume or
sug-gest that the reader does not yet have the knowledge about the relevant
topic, since otherwise writing the text would be rather pointless
However, Westney correctly points out that the suggestion of
fulfilment is by no means always present with ought to, as is witnessed by
the following example:
(8) Whenever he got a chance, Malek broke into a canter, and one
of those bursts turned into a long twilight gallop; he may have
thought we were far from home and ought to get a move on…
(Leigh Fermer, Patrick (1986) Between the Woods and the
Water, Murray, London, quoted by Westney (1995: 168))
Non-fulfilment is therefore at best a (pragmatic) implicature rather than a
(semantic) implication (i.e entailment) in the strict sense
Sentences like (8), where actualisation of the situation can be deduced from the context, are rather exceptional, however. Whether or not the sit-uation actually comes to fulfilment is not coded in the modal but is
usual-ly something to be derived extra-linguisticalusual-ly. This neutrality with re-spect to actualisation especially holds when the proposition refers to a fu-ture situation (Palmer (1990: 123))
In Degani’s (2009: 338) corpus-based study of ought to, the majority of
sentences are indeed “non-factual” (rather than “actualised” or
“counter-factual”). In such sentences, ought to simply conveys the idea that there
is a situation whose actualisation is considered desirable or expected. It
is hard to verify via corpus research whether ought to in such cases, on
top of this notion of desirability or expectation, commonly suggests a
lesser likelihood of actualisation than if should had been used. In fact, it
would not be a reliable method to check whether the likelihood of
fulfil-ment increases or decreases when replacing ought to by should in
individ-ual examples, since such judgments could only be made on a subjective basis
A more valid operationalisation would be to count the number of
in-stances of should and ought to followed by a perfect infinitive (e.g You
{should/ought to} have asked me first) or a present progressive (e.g i {should/ought to} be revising now), since these verb forms implicate
counterfactuality (but see section 5 for some complications)
2.3 Relative Frequency vs Infrequency of Epistemic Use
A number of linguists have claimed or reported that should conveys epistemicity more commonly than ought to does. Coates (1983) reports
that the ratio of epistemic versus deontic uses is roughly 1:4 in the case of
should but only roughly 1:8 in the case of ought to. This difference is
Trang 5even more pronounced in Collins’s (2009) recent corpus counts, from
which we can infer an epistemic/deontic ratio of about 1:6 for should and
of about 1:32 for ought to. According to Palmer (1987: 134), it is only
“theoretically possible to imagine ought to being used epistemically but
that seems very rarely to occur. In general ought to is interpreted
deonti-cally.” In Palmer (1990: 60) he even reports not to have found a single
example of epistemic ought to, although he acknowledges the existence of
cases of merger
In sharp contrast, Degani’s (2009: 333) corpus counts of ought to in the
FLOB and Frown corpora (representing 1990s English in the UK and the
US, respectively) reveal percentages as high as 31% and 36% for the
epistemic use. Expressed as epistemic/deontic ratios (disregarding cases
of merger), this amounts to roughly 1:1.5 for UK English and almost 1:1
for US English. Interestingly, Degani also shows that the epistemic use
of ought to seems to have increased in frequency since the early 1960s,
from 21% in the LOB corpus (UK English) and 24% in the Brown corpus
(US English), or from epistemic/deontic ratios of roughly 1:3 and roughly
1:5, respectively
We must conclude that the assessment of epistemic ought to differs
widely across studies, ranging from being only a theoretical possibility to
an interpretation which is as frequent as deontic ought to. Degani’s
(2009) study only reports recent changes in the use of ought to, so our
study will complement her study by comparing the use of ought to with
the use of should in 1990s UK English.
2.4 Other Differences Proposed in the Literature
Apart from the semantic differences mentioned in the previous
subsec-tions, it has been noted that should and ought to differ in a number of
other respects
First, and most conspicuously, should is much more frequent in use
than ought to. In the BNC, there are 111,237 occurrences of should but
only 5,979 occurrences of ought to (cf Kennedy (2002)), which amounts
to a should/ought to ratio of 19:1. Similarly, in Collins’s (2009) study
(involving different corpora), the ratio of should to ought to appears to be
19:1
Second, Celce-Murcia and Larsen-Freeman (1983: 89) claim that
deon-tic should and deondeon-tic ought to contrast with each other in that the latter
is more informal (most markedly so if it is phonologically reduced to
oughta). Not differentiating between deontic and epistemic uses, a similar
register-based difference for ought to has been noted by Collins (2009: 46): “Despite its small numbers in the present study, ought to was
found to be considerably more robust in British and American speech than writing,” with the speech/writing ratios being roughly 3:1 and 4:1,
respec-tively. (The number of epistemic uses of ought to was too low in
Collins’s study to allow a comparison between speech and writing.)
Collins (2009: 52) also notes that should is much more evenly distributed across speech and writing, but that “deontic should shows a stronger
ten-dency to be associated with the written word (…) than does epistemic
should.” This might be somewhat surprising, given that ought to has
been shown to be in serious decline (e.g Leech (2003))—one usually ex-pects to encounter archaic linguistic items in the written rather than the spoken mode. But note that many remnants of older language phases which have long disappeared from the standard language can be preserved
in dialects, which are by their nature also informal
Finally, it has been stated that “unlike should, ought to occurs mostly in
positive statements, not in negative and interrogative sentences” (Harris (1986), Aarts and Wekker (1987: 193))
3 The Present Study: Data, Parameters, Methodology 3.1 Data
For both modals, should and ought to, we made sure that at least 500
occurrences in context were extracted from corpora of British English.
Half of the occurrences are from the spoken part of the BNC, which was searched with the accompanying SARA software. Oddly, the software did not allow us to select all the written texts in the BNC in any obvious way, which led to the decision to use another corpus, the Cobuild corpus, for which we selected all the written subcorpora with British English
Trang 6lan-guage material. A difference between the BNC and the Cobuild Corpus
is that a search for should and ought in the BNC also yielded instances of
shouldn’t, shoulda, oughtn’t and oughta, whereas these forms had to be
looked up separately in Cobuild. We made sure that the number of
exam-ples of these forms extracted from Cobuild matched the proportion of the
number of base forms to the total occurrences in the corpus (about 1% for
should, about a third for ought). Table 1 provides an overview of the
to-tal number of hits for each search term and the number of hits actually
extracted. Obviously, all hits we extracted for our investigation were
chosen randomly
Table 1: Corpus Finds and Number of Examples Extracted for All
Search Terms
It can be observed from the table that should is much more frequent than
ought to in the corpora, with a 9:1 should/ought to ratio in the spoken
corpus and a 36:1 should/ought to ratio in the written corpus. These
fre-quencies confirm the general predominance of should and the relative
in-formality of ought to mentioned in section 2.4.
Removed from the data were sentences which were severely anacoluthic
and non-interpretable, as well as sentences such as those in (9)-(13),
con-taining should in a sense in which it simply could not be replaced by
ought to:
(9) a. I should like to ask Mick regarding the long service
ambu-lance personnel. (BNC, spoken discourse)
b. I should say it’s convenient for neither I should imagine.
(BNC, spoken discourse)
c When’s dad coming back?—I don’t know yet, I should think
it’ll be by the end of the month. (BNC, spoken discourse)
d I should sincerely hope not.
(Cobuild corpus, Times newspaper)
(10) a Let me know if you need anything, or if someone close to
b Always try and make up a working prototype of your ideas
should an inspection be requested.
(Cobuild corpus, UK magazines)
(11) … and I think it is absolutely critical that we should be
devot-ing our attention er, to policdevot-ing that catches criminals and
(12) a Yes, interesting you should say that, because the definition I
had was something quite the reverse
(BNC, spoken discourse)
b It is so cruel that such a thing should happen to such a nice,
c It may be coincidence that you should choose to write to me
now when what you dearly want is within reach
(Cobuild corpus, sun newspaper)
d That Oxford and Cambridge should be capable of sustaining
such a profile in the professional era is to the credit of those who run the university clubs
(Cobuild corpus, Times newspaper)
(13) So the point of conclusion is if the myth is different in the Bible then the likely explanation is that it was tampered with, but that the scribes and the people who wrote the Bible altered
the … and they changed it round why should they change this
The reason why such sentences were excluded is that we only wanted to
find factors which favour the choice for should or ought to in sentences in which they both could in principle occur. In (9a-d), should is used as an
Trang 7alternative to would after the subject i. In (10a, b), should is used in a
conditional clause to add a sense of tentativeness, i.e to suggest that the
speaker doesn’t think the actualisation of the situation is highly likely. In
(11), should is used in a that-clause depending on an expression of
neces-sity. In this sentence should alternates with the present (‘mandative’)
subjunctive. However, we did include most of the sentences in which the
modal occurs in a that-clause complementing an expression of suggestion,
advice and even occasionally necessity, since we can observe that ought
to is not wholly excluded from such contexts (although grammars do not
record this usage):
(14) a Indeed by this time Mao is specifically advocating that the
Party ought to take a more cautious and less radical
ap-proach to land reform so as to not antagonize the interests of the middle and rich peasants. (BNC, spoken discourse)
b It almost seems unfair to require that the computer ought to
be able to do things that the programmer has not foreseen
(http://www.independent.co.uk/news/business/analysis-and-features/computers-with-a-mind-of-their-own-709785.html)
In (12) above, should is used in content clauses occurring with
expres-sions indicating a (typically emotion-fuelled) personal opinion. In such
sentences an indicative form could generally be used instead of should,
but by using should, the speaker indicates that he considers the mere idea
of something as surprising or remarkable. A somewhat related use
con-cerns should after why to suggest that the speaker can’t see any obvious
reason for actualisation of the situation; cf (13), where ought to would
have been odd. Yet, most sentences with why were retained since, again,
it can be found that ought to is not completely impossible in this context,
in so far as failing to see a reason for something is often tantamount to
failing to see a (deontic or epistemic) need or necessity for it:
(15) a There is absolutely no reason why film technicians ought to
be expected to work for less than, say, a shelf stacker in a
b I don’t see why it ought to be a high turnout election.
(Corpus of Contemporary American English) The purification of our corpus examples resulted in an actual data set of
461 examples with should and 494 examples with ought to. As can be
inferred from the above discussion, deciding whether an example should
be expunged or retained was not always an easy matter. We have been as conservative as possible, thus leaving in perhaps more examples than
oth-er researchoth-ers would have done. All in all, we do not think this jeopar-dises the replicability of our study
3.2 Parameters Investigated in This Study
To the best of our knowledge, this paper investigates the potential im-pact of the largest number of parameters (i.e variables) ever considered in the comparison of two modal verbs. These are listed below, grouped for convenience by a few headings (but different groupings are of course pos-sible)
Semantic parameters:
—deontic vs epistemic vs merger
—subjective (stance-taking) vs objective (no stance-taking)
— time reference (modality is situated in the past) vs no past-time reference
Properties of the subject:
— 1st vs 2nd vs 3rd person
— animate vs inanimate
— agentive (subject control over action) vs non-agentive (lack of subject control)
Properties of the verb following the modal:
— dynamic vs stative
— present tense vs perfect tense
perfect: contracted (’ve, sometimes spelled of) vs
contracted
— simple vs progressive
— active vs passive
Trang 8Syntactic properties of the clause:
— code (use of modal to substitute entire VP, e.g You should!) vs
no code
— extraposition of the subject (e.g it should be noted that…) vs
no extraposition
— position of an adverb (if there is one) before (e.g You really
ought to…) vs after the modal (You should really…)
— clause type: embedded by think or a similar expression of cogni-tion (assume, believe, feel, it seems to me, …)
—clause type: embedded by suggest or a related item (advocate,
advise, argue, consult, insist, legislate, recommend, request, require, persuade, stipulate, etc.; also nouns like suggestion/
proposal (that) and periphrastic constructions like think it wise (that) and it is appropriate/essential (that))
—polarity: positive vs negative
— negation: external (e.g You shouldn’t be frightened = ‘It’s not necessary to be frightened’) vs internal (e.g This
privi-lege should not be abused = ‘It is necessary not to abuse
this privilege’)
—negation: contracted (-n’t) vs non-contracted
— negation: negative raising (e.g i don’t think you ought to
say that) vs otherwise
— negation: negative subject (e.g No marriage ought to be
contracted on this day) vs otherwise
— negation: near-negative (e.g We should only…) vs
other-wise
—declarative vs interrogative (including dependent questions, e.g
[boys who worry about] what moisturiser they should be us-ing)
—introduced by why (or a covert form, as in There’s no reason
_ teenagers shouldn’t earn pocket money) vs otherwise
—subject-operator inversion vs no subject-operator inversion
—coordination of modals (e.g What the trial judge can and
should do…) vs no coordination of modals
—(only for ought to) do-support vs absence of do-support
—(only for ought to) infinitive marker to vs reduced (oughta) vs
absent The quantitative results for these individual parameters are provided in the tables presented as addenda. Remember, however, that the primary aim of this study is to discover which factors have a unique contribution
to the selection of should vs ought to. Perhaps paradoxically, this can
only be achieved by considering all the parameters together: only then can
we know whether a parameter has a unique impact or whether it has to be disregarded because its effect correlates strongly to that of another param-eter whose impact is stronger (and which should therefore be retained, un-less it in turn correlates with a yet stronger parameter). Exactly how such
a multivariate analysis proceeds is explained in the next subsection
One additional semantic parameter (‘counterfactuality’) was later on as-sembled on the basis of two of the above parameters: if the verb follow-ing the modal was either a full perfect auxiliary or the progressive
auxil-iary be, the modality was considered to convey counterfactuality
fulfilment); otherwise it was not. For a motivation of this operationalisa-tion, see section 2.2, but see also section 5 for further discussion. The reason why only full perfect auxiliaries but not contracted ones were as-signed the value ‘counterfactual’ was that we knew, at the time we assem-bled this variable, that contracted perfect auxiliaries occur significantly
more frequently after should than after ought to, while we suspected, on
the basis of the linguistic literature, that a suggestion of non-fulfilment
oc-curs especially frequently with ought to. If we had included contracted
auxiliaries in the set of ‘counterfactual’ examples, a possible impact of
counterfactuality on the choice of should vs ought to would therefore
have been harder to detect, because it might have been cancelled out by the impact of contracted auxiliaries. The parameter ‘aspect’ (simple vs
progressive infinitive after the modal auxiliary) was removed from the analysis after assembling the parameter ‘counterfactuality,’ and the param-eter ‘tense’ then acquired a purely morpho-phonological interpretation (presence or absence of a reduced perfect auxiliary)
Trang 93.3 Methodology
In order to find out which of the parameters mentioned above
contrib-utes significantly to the should/ought to variation in English, we fitted a
so-called logistic regression model. This technique, which is very popular
in sociolinguistic circles (cf Goldvarb; Sankoff, Tagliamonte and Smith
(2005)), is a multivariate analysis method that measures the simultaneous
effect of one or more parameters, which may be categorical and
continu-ous in nature, on a binary outcome (in this case should vs ought to). By
means of such a multivariate technique, significant variables can be
distin-guished from non-significant ones and the relative impact of each of the
significant variables is estimated (i.e the impact of parameter X while
controlling for the effects of all other parameters included in the model).
Finally, such techniques can yield insight into the descriptive, explanatory
and predictive power of the resulting model (i.e., to what extent can the
observed variation be described, explained and predicted by the
explana-tory variables). The statistical package R 2.7.0 (R Development Core
Team (2008)) was used to conduct this statistical analysis
Before presenting the results of the logistic regression model, some
re-marks have to be made. First, for technical reasons, we reorganised
pa-rameters with more than two values, as well as papa-rameters where one of
the two values led to one or more further distinctions, to single-level,
bi-nary parameters. In doing so, we grouped those values together which
had a similar effect on the should/ought to variation, or to put it somewhat
differently, which maximised the difference between the values of the
non-binary parameters. Thus, for the parameter polarity, we decided to
regroup the values such that each sentence could be assigned either of two
values: (i) negative polarity with the negation marked on the modal
auxil-iary (i.e should not / ought not to / shouldn’t / oughtn’t to) or (ii) positive
polarity or negative polarity which is not marked on the modal auxiliary.
Second, we did not include any interaction effects in the model, since
pre-paratory analyses pointed out that such a model is corrupted by
multicol-linearity. More particularly, the estimates of the interaction terms
corre-lated heavily with the main terms, as a consequence of which the
esti-mates became unstable. Third, some of the parameters mentioned in the
previous section had to be removed from the model, as preparatory analy-ses revealed that their effect correlated heavily with the effect of other rameters (yielding a new multicollinearity problem). In particular, the pa-rameters animacy, agentivity, dynamicity, sentence type (declarative vs
interrogative), voice (active vs passive) and presence of why were
exclud-ed for that reason. For instance, the parameter sentence type correlatexclud-ed with inversion, and the parameter voice (active vs passive) correlated with agentivity, which correlated with meaning (deontic vs epistemic or merger) and with animacy, which in turn also correlated with person. In choosing which of the correlating parameters should be retained, we opted for the parameters with the strongest effect on the variation at hand. This
way, we ensured that the resulting model of the should/ought to variation
only contained parameters with a unique impact on the variation and no parameters whose effect is redundant to that of another parameter
4 Results
Our statistical model, made up of 14 non-correlating parameters, fits the data well (p = 0.14). This means that there is no reason to assume that there is a discrepancy between the variation accounted for by the model and the actual (observed) variation. The model’s predictive power, how-ever, is rather low (c = 0.69, a value closer to 0.5 (no predictive accuracy) than to 1 (full predictive accuracy)). Table 2 provides an overview of the retained parameters, ordered by individual strength (as expressed by the odds ratio)
Starting from the base-line expectation that should and ought to have an
a priori equal chance of being selected (i.e., controlling for the overall
higher frequency of should compared to ought to noted in section 3.1), we
can read the results in Table 2 as follows
First, in sentences with inversion between the subject and the operator
(e.g {should we / Ought we to} do that?), should is more than twelve
times as likely to be selected compared to when there is no inversion.
This effect is highly significant
Second, when the word following the modal is a contracted perfect
Trang 10auxiliary (’ve, sometimes spelled of, as in You {should / ought to} {’ve /
of} told me), the likelihood of that modal being should is ten times higher
than when the following word is not a contracted perfect auxiliary. This
effect is highly significant
Third, when there is no adverb or when it is positioned between the
(verbal part of the) modal and the to-infinitive (as in You {should probably
/ ought probably to} ignore this), that modal is almost four times as likely
to be should compared to when there is an adverb before the modal (as in
You probably {should / ought to} ignore this), in which case of course the
likelihood of that modal being ought to is more than four times as likely
(compared to when there is no adverb or an adverb right before the
infinitive). This effect is significant at the 0.05 level
Fourth, when the polarity is negative and expressed by means of not
or -n’t following the (verbal part of the) modal (as in We {shouldn’t /
oughtn’t to} do this), that modal is almost three times as likely to be
should compared to when the modality is positive (as in We {should / ought to} do that) or negative without the negation being marked directly
on the modal (as in i don’t think we {should / ought to} do that). This
ef-fect is highly significant
Fifth, when the modal proposition is a complement of suggest or a sim-ilar expression of suggestion, advisability, etc., should is almost three
times as likely to be selected compared to when the modal proposition is not embedded by such an item. This effect is significant at the 0.01 level
Sixth, when there is no past time reference (as in Listen to me, you
{should / ought to} get some tests done), should is more than twice as
likely to be selected compared to when there is past-time reference, as is
the case in the corpus sentence Then my father told me i ought to get
some tests done and the polyps were diagnosed (Cobuild corpus, Today
newspaper). This effect is highly significant
Seventh, when the modal proposition is not a complement of think or a similar expression of cognition, should is more than twice as likely to be
selected compared to when the proposition is embedded by such an item
(as in i think you {should / ought to} give it a try). This effect is highly
significant
Eighth, when the subject of the modal proposition is a third person (as
in he {should / ought to} apologise), should is almost twice as likely to
be selected compared to when the subject is a first or a second person (as
in {i / you / we} {should / ought to} apologise). This effect is highly
sig-nificant
All other parameters are not significant—notably, this is the case for meaning (epistemicity/merger vs deonticity) and for counterfactuality—or were left out of the model because they correlated with one or more of the other parameters
5 Discussion
Our model of the unique factors governing the choice between should and ought to allows us to describe this variation fairly parsimoniously in
terms of eight significant factors and six more factors whose impact turns
Parameter and Its Setting for Selection of should Odds Ratio Significance
Adverb: none or right after the auxiliary 3.9 *
Modal proposition embedded by an item like suggest: yes 2.7 **
Modal proposition embedded by a cognition item: no 2.1 ***
Table 2: Statistical Model of the Variation between should and Ought
to, with Predictors for should, Odds Ratios and Significance
Levels (‘***’: p < 0.001; ‘**’: p < 0.01; ‘*’: p < 0.05; ‘n.s.’:
not significant); ‘n.a.’ = not applicable