Who Needs Emotions The Brain Meets the Robot - Fellous & Arbib Part 10 potx

20 210 0
Who Needs Emotions The Brain Meets the Robot - Fellous & Arbib Part 10 potx

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống

Thông tin tài liệu

164 brains Figure 6.1. A tentative illustration of the many interactions between two agents. Each agent builds in the brain a representation of both his or her own intended actions, using internal cues like beliefs and desires, and the potential actions of the other agent. These partly overlapping representations are used by each agent to build a set of predictions and estimates about the social consequences of the represented actions, if and when they would be exe- cuted. When an action comes to execution, it is perceived by the other agent as a set of social signals which do or do not confirm predictions and possibly modify beliefs and desires. Beliefs and desires of Agent A Beliefs and desires of Agent B Execution of action Execution of action Representation of self- generated action Representation of observed action Representation of observed action Social signals from Agent B Social signals from Agent A Who ? Who ? Estimation of social consequences Estimation of social consequences Representation of self- generated action in the pattern of cortical connectivity could alter the shape of the networks corresponding to different representations or the relative intensity of acti- vation in the areas composing these networks. Although little is known on the functional aspects of cortical connectivity underlying the formation of these networks and, a fortiori, their dysfunction in schizophrenia, several studies have pointed to the prefrontal cortex as one of the possible sites for how do we decipher others’ minds? 165 perturbed activation (e.g., Weinberger & Berman, 1996). Because prefron- tal areas normally exert an inhibitory control on other areas involved in vari- ous aspects of motor and sensorimotor processing, alteration of this control in schizophrenic patients might result in aberrant representations of actions and emotions. Referring to the diagram in Figure 6.1, one of the two agents would become “schizophrenic” if, due to an alteration in the pattern of con- nectivity of the corresponding networks, the degree of overlap between the representations in the brain increased in such a way that the representations would become indistinguishable from each other. The pattern of misattribu- tion in this agent would be a direct consequence of this alteration: for ex- ample, decreased self attribution if frontal inhibition were too strong or increased if it were too weak. References Adams, L., Guz, A., Innes, J. A., & Murphy, K. (1987). The early circulatory and ventilatory response to voluntary and electrically induced exercise in man. Jour- nal of Physiology, 383, 19–30. Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. R. (1998). The human amygdala in social judgment. Nature, 393, 470–474. Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Damasio, H., & Damasio, A. (1994). Impaired recogni- tion of emotion in facial expression following bilateral damage to the human amygdala. Nature, 372, 669–672. Baudouin, J. Y., Martin, F., Tiberghien, G., Verlut, I., & Franck, N. (2002). Selec- tive attention to facial emotion and identity in schizophrenia. Neuropsychologia, 40, 503–511. Berenbaum, H., & Oltmanns, T. F. (1992). Emotional experience and expression in schizophrenia and depression. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 101, 37–44. Bruce, V., & Young, A. (1986). Understanding face recognition. British Journal of Psychology, 77, 305–327. Chadwick, P., & Birchwood, M. (1994). The omnipotence of voices. A cognitive approach to auditory hallucinations. British Journal of Psychiatry, 164, 190–201. Czibra, G., Gergely, G., Biro, S., Koos, O., & Brockbank, M. (1999). Goal attribu- tion without agency cues: The perception of “pure reason” in infancy. Cogni- tion, 72, 237–267. Daprati, E., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Proust, J., Pacherie, E., Dalery, J., & Jeannerod, M. (1997). Looking for the agent. An investigation into consciousness of ac- tion and self-consciousness in schizophrenic patients. Cognition, 65, 71–86. Dasser, V., Ulbaek, I., & Premack, D. (1989). The perception of intention. Science, 243, 365–367. David, A. S. (1994). The neuropsychological origin of auditory hallucinations. In A. S. David & J. C. Cutting (Eds.), The neuropsychology of schizophrenia (pp. 269–313). Hove, UK: Erlbaum. 166 brains Davies, M., & Stone, T. (Eds.) (1995). Folk psychology. The theory of mind debate. Oxford: Blackwell. Decety, J., Grezes, J., Costes, N., Perani, D., Jeannerod, M., Procyk, E., Grassi, F., & Fazio, F. (1997). Brain activity during observation of action. Influence of action content and subject’s strategy. Brain, 120, 1763–1777. Decety, J, Jeannerod, M., Durozard, D., & Baverel, G. (1993). Central activation of autonomic effectors during mental simulation of motor actions in man. Jour- nal of Physiology, 461, 549–563. Decety, J., Jeannerod, M., & Prablanc, C. (1989). The timing of mentally repre- sented actions. Behavioural Brain Research, 34, 35–42. Decety, J., Perani, D., Jeannerod, M., Bettinardi, V., Tadary, B., Woods, R., Mazziotta, J. C., & Fazio, F. (1994). Mapping motor representations with PET. Nature, 371, 600–602. Dierks, T., Linden, D. E. J., Jandl, M., Formisano, E., Goebel, R., Lanferman, H., & Singer, W. (1999). Activation of the Heschl’s gyrus during auditory hallucina- tions. Neuron, 22, 615–621. Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Pavesi, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (1995). Motor facilitation during action observation. A magnetic stimulation study. Journal of Neurophysiology, 73, 2608–2611. Feinberg, T. E., Rifkin, A., Schaffer, C., & Walker, E. (1986). Facial discrimination and emotional recognition in schizophrenia and affective disorders. Archives of General Psychiatry, 43, 276–279. Frak, V. G., Paulignan, Y., & Jeannerod, M. (2001). Orientation of the opposition axis in mentally simulated grasping. Experimental Brain Research, 136, 120–127. Franck, N., Farrer, C., Georgieff, N., Marie-Cardine, M., Daléry, J. D’Amato, T., & Jeannerod, M. (2001). Defective recognition of one’s own actions in schizo- phrenic patients. American Journal of Psychiatry, 158, 454–459. Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Science, 12, 493–501. Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external reality. A “who” system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 465–477. Gérardin, E., Sirigu, A., Lehéricy, S., Poline, J B., Gaymard, B., Marsault, C., Agid, Y., & Le Bihan, D. (2000). Partially overlapping neural networks for real and imagined hand movements. Cerebral Cortex, 10, 1093–1104. Gergely, G., Nadasdy, Z., Czibra, G., & Biro, S. (1995). Taking the intentional stance at 12 months of age. Cognition, 56, 165–193. Goldie, P. (1999). How we think of others’ emotions. Mind and Language, 14, 394– 423. Gould, L. N. (1949). Auditory hallucinations in subvocal speech: Objective study in a case of schizophrenia. Journal of Nervous and Mental Diseases, 109, 418–427. Grafton, S. T., Arbib, M. A., Fadiga, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). Localization of grasp representations in humans by PET: 2. Observation compared with imagi- nation. Experimental Brain Research, 112, 103–111. how do we decipher others’ minds? 167 Haxby, J. V., Hoffman, E. A., & Gobbini, I. (2000). The distributed human neural system for face perception. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4, 223–233. Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology, 57, 243–259. Hoffman, E. A., & Haxby, J. V. (2000). Distinct representations of eye gaze and identity in the distributed human neural system for face perception. Nature America, 3, 80–84. Ingvar, D., & Philipsson, L. (1977). Distribution of the cerebral blood flow in the dominant hemisphere during motor ideation and motor performance. Annals of Neurology, 2, 230–237. Janet, P. (1937). Les troubles de la personnalité sociale. Annales Médico-Psycho- logiques, II, 149–200. Jeannerod, M. (1993). A theory of representation-driven actions. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The perceived self: Ecological and interpersonal sources of self-knowledge (pp. 89– 101). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jeannerod, M. (1994). The representing brain. Neural correlates of motor inten- tion and imagery. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17, 187–245. Jeannerod, M. (1995). Mental imagery in the motor context. Neuropsychologia, 33, 1419–1432. Jeannerod, M. (1999). To act or not to act: Perspectives on the representation of actions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 52A, 1–29. Jeannerod, M. (2001). Neural simulation of action: A unifying mechanism for motor cognition. Neuroimage, 14, S103–S109. Jeannerod, M., & Frak, V. G. (1999). Mental simulation of action in human sub- jects. Current Opinions in Neurobiology, 9, 735–739. Johansson, G. (1973). Visual perception of biological motion and a model for its analysis. Perception and Psychophysics, 14, 201–211. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). The simulation heuristic. In P. Slovic, D. Kahneman, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kanwisher, N., McDermott, J., & Chun, M. M. (1997). The fusiform face area: A module in human extrastriate cortex specialized for face perception. Journal of Neuroscience, 17, 4302–4311. Kluwer, H., & Bucy, P. C. (1939). Preliminary analysis of the function of parietal lobes in monkeys. Archives of Neurological Psychiatry, 42, 979–997. Krogh, A., & Lindhard, J. (1913). The regulation of respiration and circulation during the initial stages of muscular work. Journal of Physiology, 47, 112–136. Lacquaniti, F., Terzuolo, C., & Viviani, P. (1983). The law relating kinematic and figural aspects of drawing movements. Acta Psychologica, 54, 115–130. Lang, P. (1979). A bioinformational theory of emotional imagery. Psychophysiol- ogy, 16, 495–512. Levenson, R. W., Ekman, P., & Friesen, W. V. (1990). Voluntary facial action gen- erates emotion-specific autonomic nervous system activity. Psychophysiology, 27, 363–384. 168 brains Lhermitte, F. (1983). Utilisation behaviour and its relation to lesions of the frontal lobes. Brain, 106, 237–255. Liberman, A. M., & Mattingly, I. G. (1985). The motor theory of perception of speech revisited. Cognition, 21, 1–36. Lipps, T. (1903). Aesthetik: Psychologie des schönen un der kunst. Hamburg: Voss. Lotze, R. H. (1852). Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele. Leipzig: Weidmann’sche Buchhandlung. Neisser, U. (1993). The self perceived. In U. Neisser (Ed.), The perceived self. Eco- logical and interpersonal sources of self-knowledge (pp. 3–21). Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Nelson, C. A. (1987). The recognition of facial expression in the first two years of life. Mechanisms of development. Child Development, 58, 889–909. Paccalin, C., & Jeannerod, M. (2000). Changes in breathing during observation of effortful actions. Brain Research, 862, 194–200. Parsons, L. M. (1994). Temporal and kinematic properties of motor behavior re- flected in mentally simulated action. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 20, 709–730. Pigman, G. W. (1995). Freud and the history of empathy. International Journal of Psycho-Analysis, 76, 237–256. Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., & Fogassi, L. (1995). Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141. Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Matelli, M., Bettinardi, V., Paulesu, E., Perani, D., & Fazio, G. (1996). Localization of grasp representations in humans by PET: 1. Obser- vation versus execution. Experimental Brain Research, 111, 246–252. Roth, M., Decety, J., Raybaudi, M., Massarelli, R., Delon-Martin, C., Segebarth, C., Morand, S., Gemignani, A., Décorps, M., & Jeannerod, M. (1996). Pos- sible involvement of primary motor cortex in mentally simulated movement. A functional magnetic resonance imaging study. Neuroreport, 7, 1280–1284. Ruby, P., & Decéty, J. (2001). Effect of subjective perspective taking during simula- tion of action: A PET investigation of agency. Nature Neurosciences, 4, 546–550. Schneider, K. (1955). Klinische Psychopathologie. Stuttgart: Thieme Verlag. Shiffrar, M., & Freyd, J. J. (1990). Apparent motion of the human body. Psychologi- cal Science, 1, 257–264. Silbersweig, D. A., Stern, E., Frith, C., Cahill, C., Holmes, A., Grootoonk, S., Sea- ward, J., McKenna, P., Chua, S. E., Schnorr, L., Jones, T., & Frackowiak, R. S. J. (1995). A functional neuroanatomy of hallucinations in schizophrenia. Nature, 378, 176–179. Sirigu, A., Duhamel, J R., Cohen, L., Pillon, B., Dubois, B., & Agid, Y. (1996). The mental representation of hand movements after parietal cortex damage. Science, 273, 1564–1568. Stone, V. E., Baron-Cohen, S., Calder, A., Keane, J., & Young, A. (2003). Acquired theory of mind impairments in individuals with bilateral amygdala lesions. Neuropsychologia, 41, 209–220. Titchener, E. B. (1908). Lectures on the elementary psychology of feeling and atten- tion. New York: MacMillan. how do we decipher others’ minds? 169 Viviani, P. (1990). Common factors in the control of free and constrained move- ments. In M. Jeannerod (Ed.), Motor representation and control, Attention and Performance (Vol. XIII, pp. 345–373). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Viviani, P., & Stucchi, N. (1992). Biological movements look uniform. Evidence of motor–perceptual interactions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Human Per- ception and Performance, 18, 603–623. Weinberger, D. R., & Berman, K. F. (1996). Prefrontal function in schizophrenia: Confounds and controversies. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 351, 1495–1503. Zajonc, R. B. (1985). Emotion and facial efference: A theory reclaimed. Science, 228, 15–21. This page intentionally left blank PART III ROBOTS This page intentionally left blank Affect and Proto-Affect in Effective Functioning andrew ortony, donald a. norman, and william revelle 7 We propose a functional model of effective functioning that depends on the interplay of four relatively independent domains, namely, affect (value), motivation (action tendencies), cognition (meaning), and behavior (the organism’s actions). These domains of functioning all need to be considered at each of three levels of information processing: the reactive, the routine, and the reflective levels. The reactive level is pri- marily a hard-wired releaser of fixed action patterns and an interrupt generator, limited to such things as processing simple stimuli and initi- ating approach and avoidance behaviors. This level has only proto-affect. The routine level is the locus of unconscious, uninterpreted expectations and well-learned automatized activity, and is characterized by aware- ness, but not self-awareness. This level is the locus of primitive and unconscious emotions. The reflective level is the home of higher-order cognitive functions, including metacognition, consciousness, and self- reflection, and features full-fledged emotions. In this framework, we characterize personality as a self-tunable system comprised of the tem- poral patterning of affect, motivation, cognition, and behavior. Person- ality traits are a reflection of the various parameter settings that govern the functioning of these different domains at all three processing lev- els. Our model constitutes a good way of thinking about the design of emotions in computational artifacts of arbitrary complexity that must [...]... refer to as “proto-affect.” The realm of proto-affect is restricted to the here and now, as opposed to the future or the past The second, routine, level is primarily concerned with the execution of well-learned behaviors At this level, affect begins to show some of the features of what we would ordinarily call emotions but in a rather limited and primitive manner These “primitive emotions can involve... example, the newt, motivated to copulate (below the water), is also motivated to breathe (above the water); sometimes the behavior can be modified to accommodate both drives, but otherwise, the more critical will dominate and temporarily inhibit the other (Halliday, 1980) As for affect, our proposal is that at the reactive level there is only the simplest form of affect imaginable, what we call “proto-affect.”... (Kahneman & Miller, 1986) The strength of these expectations together with the intensity of valence associated with the current and expected states influence the strength of the ensuing feelings Expectations might also arise from some kind of continuity-of-experience mechanism—an implicit belief that the future is not apt to deviate much from the recent past However, whether the expectations are learned... at the routine level Given our view that the routine level allows for some representation of the future as well as the present, four elementary cognitive categories emerge as a result of crossing these two levels of time with the two levels of valence (positive and negative) These four categories lie at the heart of the rudimentary, primitive emotions that arise at the routine level In terms of the. .. cognitively elaborated, full-fledged emotion (reflective level) Although these different kinds of affective state vary in the degree to which they involve components of prototypical emotions, many are still emotion-like, albeit not very good examples (Ortony, Clore, & Foss, 1987) The graded nature of the concept of emotion is readily accommodated by our account partly because the specificity of an affective... Rather, they vary in their typicality, with some cases being better examples than others Thus, we propose that the best examples of emotions, which we often refer to as “full-fledged emotions, ” are interpretations of lower-level feelings and occur only at the reflective level, influenced by a combination of contributions from the behavioral, motivational, 178 robots and cognitive domains At the middle, routine,... valence to stimuli At the same time, these reactive-level affective signals are so intimately related to behavioral (especially motor) responses and to the motivation to approach or avoid a stimulus that it makes little sense to try to distinguish them from one another Throughout evolutionary history, the specificity of the automatic response systems has grown so much that, in the human, there are specific,... Affect at the Routine Level: Primitive Emotions The core of the routine level is the execution of well-learned routines— “automatic” as opposed to “controlled” processes (e.g., Schneider & Shiffrin, 1977) In contrast to the reactive level, the routine level is capable of a wide range of processes, from conditioning involving expectancies to quite sophisticated symbolic processing This is the level... although there is no consciousness at the routine level, awareness is an important cognitive aspect of it Earlier, we defined cognition as the domain associated with meaning and affect as the domain associated with value One of the things of which we can be (cognitively) aware is (affective) feeling; but although there is awareness at the routine level, there is no self-awareness This is because self-awareness... Since routine-level processes cannot examine their own operations, self-awareness is possible only at the reflective level Expectations play an important role at the routine level Routine-level processes are able to correct for simple deviations from expectations, although when the discrepancy becomes too large, reflective-level control is required Consider the case of driving an automobile If the routine . “proto-affect.” The realm of proto-affect is re- stricted to the here and now, as opposed to the future or the past. The second, routine, level is primarily concerned with the execution of well-learned. (Kahneman & Miller, 1986). The strength of these expectations to- gether with the intensity of valence associated with the current and expected states influence the strength of the ensuing. modification of output, but none of the activity is cognitive in nature—there is no cognition at the reac- tive level. Furthermore, at the reactive level, the other three domains of functioning—affect,

Ngày đăng: 10/08/2014, 02:21

Từ khóa liên quan

Tài liệu cùng người dùng

  • Đang cập nhật ...

Tài liệu liên quan