A Companion to the History of Economic Thought - Chapter 39 ppt

14 391 0
A Companion to the History of Economic Thought - Chapter 39 ppt

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống

Thông tin tài liệu

RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 655 CHAPTER THIRTY- NINE Research in the History of Economic Thought as a Vehicle for the Defense and Criticism of Orthodox Economics John Lodewijks It is almost impossible to attend a gathering of North American historians of eco- nomic thought without getting the uncomfortable feeling that many are there to grieve over the corpse. Many come to lament a time when economics was different, when it was better, and when it had not been perverted by formalism and higher mathematics. Many grieve for John Maynard Keynes and Commons, for Friedrich Hayek and Mitchell and Ludwig von Mises. Bradley W. Bateman (in Morgan and Rutherford, 1998, p. 29) It is a striking fact that conferences in history of economic thought attract Austrians, Marxists, Radical political economists, Sraffians, institutionalists and post-Keynesians in disproportionate numbers, all non-neoclassicals or even anti-neoclassicals who have no place else to go to talk to scholars outside their narrow intellectual circles. Mark Blaug (2001, p. 147) 39.1 BALANCING THE HISTORY OF ECONOMICS Many students throughout the world were introduced to the history of eco- nomics through Robert Heilbroner’s immensely popular The Worldly Philosophers, 656 J. LODEWIJKS originally published in 1953 and now in its seventh edition, with over four million copies sold to date. Geoffrey Harcourt (2001, p. 167) claims that it is the best introduction to the lives and contributions of the great economists ever written. The chapters on Marx and Veblen are delightfully entertaining and beautifully crafted. But is it a “balanced” history of economics? It was written by an author who, in this work and in numerous other publications, displays a highly critical stance toward mainstream economics. Heilbroner (1979, p. 197) alleges that modern economics “is shallow and poor rather than deep and rich” and disap- pointing in comparison with the economics of earlier periods. Modern economics “has nothing to compare with the ‘magnificent dynamics’ of the Classicists” and Heilbroner cannot discover in modern economics a depth or breadth comparable with earlier periods, or any great overall vision that illuminates issues. Critics maintain that his history is biased, focusing too heavily on the economics of socialists, Marxists, and the “Underworld of Economics.” Mark Skousen (2001) wrote The Making of Modern Economics specifically to “right” this imbalance. Like Heilbroner, this text is also provocative and entertain- ing, with scandals of various sorts embellishing the lives of the great thinkers. Yet it would be difficult to call this a balanced history either. It is an Austrian history of economics, where Adam Smith’s self-regulating system of natural liberty and competition triumphs against the forces of socialist interventionism. Each episode in the history of economics is evaluated in terms of what was added or subtracted from Smith’s system, and in so doing the “power of neo- classical analysis” is revealed. The title of chapter six is “Marx madness plunges economics into a new dark age,” and there Marx is chastised as a “demonic genius,” an “anti-semitic Jew” who wrote “satanic verses,” and ultimately a “dismal failure.” In chapter seven, “Menger and the Austrians reverse the tide” and resurrect Smith’s system of natural liberty. In chapter thirteen, “The Keynes mutiny: capitalism faces its greatest challenge,” one might be excused for pre- suming that capitalism’s greatest challenge was the Great Depression. Not so. It is Keynes. Skousen begins the chapter with a quote that claims that “Keynesian economics is . . . the most serious blow that the authority of orthodox economics has yet suffered.” It was then left to Milton Friedman “to reverse the Keynesian tide and reestablish the virtues of neoclassical economics” (Skousen, 2001, p. 397). Should we be concerned about the way in which these histories of thought are written? For example, there is not even a mention of the seminal research of either Samuel Hollander or Philip Mirowski in the Skousen book. Nor is the intellectual history of Adam Smith, written by Jacob Viner and Donald Winch, acknowledged. Winch’s work is explicitly against attempts to recruit Smith retro- actively into some ideological category and association with extreme laissez-faire and libertarianism. One response is to note that Heilbroner and Skousen provide introductions to the subject, written in provocative ways, to entice students toward further study where they then go on to do “real” history of economics. Skousen (2001, p. 5) freely admits that his “book is not a normal history. It is candidly, an irreverent, passionate, sometimes humorous, and often highly opinionated account of the lives and theories of famous economists.” A related point is that these texts relate to the teaching of the history of economics, not research at the frontier of the sub-discipline. Alternatively, our friends from literary criticism might also RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 657 argue that all history is socially constructed and there is no objective truth out there to be discovered. The writing of histories is a creative enterprise and the texts above presumably satisfy the needs of their interpretive communities. Finally, perhaps the concern about balance and objectivity is a storm in a teacup. Will not students easily discern the biases of these texts and take them with a grain of salt? Students of Warren Samuels’s history of thought class could clearly discern the ideological agenda behind texts by E. K. Hunt and Ray Canterbery. These texts were intentionally and explicitly critical of the way in which economic thought has developed. In contrast, Henry Spiegel’s The Growth of Economic Thought was perceived to have no agenda to push and no intention to promote any particular school of thought (Medema and Samuels, 2001, p. 295). 39.2 RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMICS One could tell a story of how research in the history of economics has been colored by the stance that various scholars have taken toward orthodox eco- nomics. The written history could then be regarded as a vehicle for the defense or criticism of orthodoxy. The work of Terence Hutchison seems a natural place to start. Since The Significance and Basic Postulates of Economic Theory first appeared in 1938, the central methodological themes of Hutchison’s research has remained essentially unchanged (Hands, 2001, pp. 536–40). For example, part I of his 1953 Review of Economic Doctrines, 1870–1929, was entitled “The architects of equilib- rium economics and their main critics” and in the Preface he was again alluding to “a lessening in the realism and relevance” of economic analysis. Hutchison has long complained of the failure of economics to conform to the canons of positive science. Economic theory rests on weak epistemological foundations, employs highly unrealistic assumptions, and is therefore incapable of generating empiric- ally falsifiable predictions. Practitioners are too preoccupied with refinements and elaborations of abstract general theories. These themes were highlighted in his 1977 Knowledge and Ignorance in Economics and in numerous other publica- tions. Hutchison, an outsider to the profession, has been intensely critical of economics. Mark Blaug has followed in Hutchison’s footsteps. Blaug had two supervisors – George Stigler and Terence Hutchison – at Columbia and both were mentors of sorts. Blaug is highly critical of the current state of economic knowledge, and emphasizes the need for more determined efforts to produce theories that yield unambiguously refutable implications and then to confront those implications with the facts. He rails against the disease of formalism in modern economics, where the form of an argument dominates substance and content. Modern theory then ceases to make any descriptive claim about actual economic systems, and becomes a purely formal apparatus, a mathematical thought-experiment. Blaug (2001, p. 160) alleges that Debreu’s Theory of Value is “probably the most arid and pointless book in the entire literature of economics” and that the “history of general equilibrium theory from Walras to Arrow–Debreu has been a journey down a blind alley, and it is historians of economic thought who seem to have finally hammered down the nails in this coffin.” 658 J. LODEWIJKS Two aspects of Blaug’s work in this context are interesting to observe. First, while Blaug is critical of orthodoxy, he has very limited sympathy with heterodox critics. His damning critique of the Marxian and Sraffian research programs is well known. He also has little time for post-modernist approaches. Secondly, Roger Backhouse (in Medema and Samuels, 2001, p. 21) has charted Blaug’s intellectual journey through the various editions of his Economic Theory in Retro- spect. What is interesting is Blaug’s “change of mind” over the years on Ricardo, Sraffa’s interpretation of Ricardo, macroeconomics, and the value of general equilibrium analysis. Blaug on general equilibrium, for example, has moved from supporter to critic. (A similar “change of mind” over Ricardo happened to Samuel Hollander. At one time he subscribed to Sraffa’s reading of Ricardo, but the “weight of evidence” led him to abandon this interpretation.) Philip Mirowski’s More Heat than Light (1990) has generated enormous interest in the field and considerable controversy (see De Marchi, 1993). Mirowski high- lights deep conceptual problems in the foundations of economic science through its perverse attempts to emulate physics. His account of the marginal revolution is one of the delayed and distorted adoption of ideas from the physical sciences. His book is a severe historical critique of neoclassical economics, which claims that economics today is outdated physics and that economics should abandon physics (see Leonard, in De Marchi, 1993). Rizvi has outlined what he calls Mirowski’s “palpable and very personal opposition to mainstream economics” (p. 215). The almost mocking attitude to Paul Samuelson is a clear example of this. Mirowski notes that he “fully anticipated the wrath of the orthodox neo- classical economics profession. Had I been trying to ingratiate myself with that crew, I should have done things differently . . .” (De Marchi, 1993, p. 306). In sharp contrast to the above critiques of economics, but no less controversial, stands the work of Samuel Hollander. Hollander’s thesis is that the history of economics shows strong continuity. Classical and neoclassical economists both share essentially the same approach to pricing, distribution, and allocation theory. Hollander claims, for example, that Ricardo’s “cost-price analysis is pre- eminently an analysis of the allocation of scarce resources, proceeding in terms of general equilibrium, with allowance for final demand, and the interdepend- ence of factor and commodity markets.” Hollander’s interpretation of classical economics has irked reviewers from the Sraffian camp and from the anti-Neo- Ricardians, such as Denis O’Brien, Terry Peach, and Terence Hutchison, the latter commenting on Hollander’s “extraordinary capacity . . . for dismissing, disregard- ing, or devaluing evidence, however plain and unambiguous, that conflicts with the Hollander interpretation” (Lodewijks, 1995, p. 143). A large part of the furor over Hollander’s approach is its identification with “Whig” history. The clearest exponent of this is Paul Samuelson (1987, p. 52), who proposes “that history of economics more purposefully reorient itself toward studying the past from the standpoint of the present state of economic science.” He alleges that “within any classical economist there is to be discerned a mod- ern economist trying to be born.” The implicit assumption is that knowledge is cumulative, and you judge past scholars in terms of how much they contributed to the present state of understanding. Others who adopt this framework are RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 659 George Stigler, Donald Walker, and A. M. C. Waterman. Critics of Whig history say that it is a distorted historical reconstruction, where thinkers are examined out of context. Moreover, it serves to justify and legitimize modern economics with a search for pedigrees and precursors. The research in the history of economics undertaken by Hutchison, Blaug, Mirowski, and Hollander has been pathbreaking. These scholars also have estab- lished very strong positions as either defenders or critics of modern economics. If our craft is identified with attacks on mainstream economics, this may partly explain our declining fortunes in the profession. It may generate an overall negat- ive impression of our research and confirm suspicions about the field. The end result is that it reduces the chances of graduate students gaining some acquaint- ance with the history of their discipline as an essential component of their train- ing and some familiarity with exemplary work in the field. Also, if one comes to the history of economics with a view that economics is fundamentally misguided or, alternatively, that we can find a supply-and-demand model in every past thinker if we look hard enough, then that colors the historical interpretation. In the next section, we deal with schools of thought where these concerns have added importance. 39.3 HETERODOXY AND THE HISTORY OF THOUGHT Roy Weintraub has taken a strong position that work in the Austrian, Marxian, institutionalist, or post-Keynesian tradition cannot be regarded as legitimate history of economic thought. In his view, citing long-dead economists and em- ploying historical references does not generate historical scholarship. Weintraub notes that the history of the discipline is being increasingly told by those who are hostile to the discipline and its major contributors, and is being used to justify or criticize the role of individuals or schools. The history of economics has become a home for heterodox traditions that are antithetical to the mainstream. Many of these issues were explored in a conference on “The future of the history of economics” held at Duke University in April 2001 (Weintraub, 2002). A survey of British historians of economic thought undertaken by Roger Backhouse for the conference revealed that 54 percent identified themselves as heterodox, but only 11 percent identified themselves as neoclassical. Many entered the history of economics due to dissatisfaction with conventional eco- nomics. One implication is that university funding in Britain, which depends on a research assessment exercise that ranks research, will discriminate against his- torians of thought and heterodox economists who do not publish in mainstream “top” journals. Aiko Ikeo delivered a paper that showed that the majority of historians of thought in Japan were also critical of mainstream economics, while in many Eastern European countries the history of economics was taught in the Marxist tradition. Anthony Brewer examined the Marxist tradition and concluded that “Much, perhaps most, of the literature on Marx’s economics . . . is therefore of little use to the historian of economics.” Ronald Meek and Maurice Dobb are 660 J. LODEWIJKS two well-known Marxist historians of thought. Meek was initially an uncritical Marxist and a supporter of Joseph Stalin, who later was skeptical of Marxism, and became more an intellectual historian, albeit one strongly influenced by Marxian themes and approaches. The transformation can be documented in the various editions of his Studies in the Labour Theory of Value. Dobb regarded economics “as a tool of the working people in their struggle for social liberation” (Medema and Samuels, 2001, p. 83). His Theories of Value and Distribution since Adam Smith was the first history-of-thought text in the light of the Sraffian revolution. Sraffa’s “corn model” interpretation of Ricardo led to a rational reconstruction of the history of economics to demonstrate that there was a “surplus” tradition, in sharp contrast to mainstream economics. Among Sraffians, this interpretation of Ricardo is an integral part of their attempt to overthrow neoclassical value, distribution, and growth theory. The Sraffian approach to classical economics, often labeled neo-Ricardian, has elicited much debate, and this continues in trenchant claims of bias in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and, more recently, in the Elgar Companion to Classical Economics (Blaug, 1999; Peach, 1999; Hollander, 2000). The conference paper by Christina Marcuzzo and Annalisa Rosselli illustrated how Italian his- tory of thought from the late 1960s to the early 1980s was strongly influenced by Marx and Sraffa. History of thought in Italy became synonymous with doing nonmainstream economics. Indeed, it is alleged that the neo-Ricardians have cornered some of the leading European academic journals in the field. Malcolm Rutherford (1994) has written extensively on old and new American institutionalism. Post-Keynesian approaches, broadly interpreted, have long been popular in many other countries. Sheila Dow takes a more upbeat perspective on the use of history by post-Keynesians and on heterodox economics generally. She notes that some heterodox economists may use history of thought as a vehicle for supporting their views, but most use it to understand historical ideas better and to assist the development of theory. Post-Keynesians embed the history of economics in their theoretical and policy discussions. Sraffians more than post- Keynesians make contributions to the history of economics; the latter rarely go back earlier in time than the contributions of Keynes and Kalecki. Harcourt (2001) contains various intellectual biographies, tributes, and eulogies in the post- Keynesian tradition. Post-Keynesianism, he says, “is an extremely broad church. The overlaps at each end of a long spectrum of views are marginal, reflecting little more than a shared hostility towards mainstream neoclassical economics and methodology” (2001, p. 263). Harcourt provides glimpses of the intellectual history of Joan Robinson and her circle – Austin Robinson, Richard Kahn, Piero Sraffa, Nicholas Kaldor, Michal Kalecki, Dick Goodwin, Maurice Dobb, Luigi Pasinetti, and, of course, John Maynard Keynes. Yet in the essays one finds very few critical comments on the contributions of this “circle.” Indeed, it is quite a challenge to find any. Whereas for the orthodox economist the research frontier is clearly being advanced in the near present, for some heterodox schools the research frontier is still largely discernible in the works of the founders or their immediate followers. At some point, as the approach becomes less popular, the profession’s attention moves away from developing and elaborating the key RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 661 insights of the founders. Scholars sympathetic to heterodoxy then have to go back in time to “pick up the torch” and run with it. Peter Boettke has been quite critical of the use made by Austrians of the history of economics. He thinks that it is often used for ideological purposes and hagio- graphy, and that it is too passionate and committed. Murray Rothbard’s treat- ment of Adam Smith is best viewed as a libertarian diatribe, rather than a careful examination of Smith’s system. However, he also gives examples of where Aus- trians have produced high-quality history of thought, and mentions the work of Karen Vaughn, Bruce Caldwell, and Laurence Moss. Boettke calculates that 5 percent of History of Political Economy articles and 6.8 percent of Journal of the History of Economic Thought articles have been written by or about Austrian economists. He also estimates that around one in four to one in five articles in specialist Austrian economics journals are works in the history of economics. Many of the books written by Austrian school economists contain substantial historical material (Medema and Samuels, 2001, pp. 117–28). Mark Blaug (2001) argues that the history of economics appeals to a different type of mind from that of the average mainstream economist. It attracts the more philosophic, less mathematically inclined mind and the more policy-relevant economist, who feels that the discipline has a rationale of improving society. In other words, the sub-discipline is a haven for heterodoxy! Is this inherently undesirable? Certainly, in an increasingly homogenized discipline, it provides an avenue through which dissent can be expressed. Perhaps it is one role of his- torians of thought to provide discomfiture: “The task of the historian of social theory is not . . . either to celebrate, to bury – or even merely to understand – the past; its task is to discomfort the present” (Lowry, 1991, p. 136). Historians of thought present the work of a Nobel Laureate in an historical perspective that is at variance with the (self-serving) recollections of the Nobelist himself. Or they outline the historical antecedents and developments that have been hidden, or rewritten in more palatable forms, in textbooks that show a basic continuity of research endeavor that leads to the present. Or they raise uncomfortable questions about the military origins of game theory. Criticism may help to reform the discipline, but if the history of the subject is being increasingly told by those who are hostile to the discipline and its major contributors, then it should come as no surprise that the history of economic thought will be increasingly marginalized in the profession. Conversely, the smaller number of historians of thought who are sympathetic to modern eco- nomics seem to have a greater proclivity at placing their research in mainstream journals. John Creedy, who works on technical issues relating to the historical development of neoclassical economics, is a case in point. Samuel Hollander is another obvious example. Overall, the erosion of the position of the history of economics in the larger discipline of economics is clear. The subject is no longer taught at many institutions. However, there is a tricky issue of causality here. Is the history of economic thought marginalized because it is dominated by hetero- dox economists, or are heterodox economists naturally attracted to nonorthodox, and hence marginalized, research endeavors? Indeed, some could argue that we should be making more overtures to heterodox economists, as they at least 662 J. LODEWIJKS appreciate our craft while the profession as a whole turns away from any historical interest. Since orthodox scholars tend to be more Whiggish, perhaps those with a heterodox approach have a comparative advantage in our field, as better-quality history of thought results from those who do not begin with Whig history. One could ask why there are not more orthodox scholars in the sub-discipline. One hypothesis, yet to be fully explored, relates to the nature of Ph.D. research. Is it the case that those who completed a mainstream thesis topic, and who were relatively successful in terms of publications and citations in mainstream journals, are more likely to defend orthodoxy when they later are persuaded to work in the history-of-thought field? I can think of a few counter-examples, but not that many. The issues of objectivity and bias still remain. Look at Groenewegen and McFarlane (1990). The strength of the book is undoubtedly its emphasis on the diversity of sources and dissent in Australian economics. Australian economics sprang from a varied mixture of sources – academics, public servants, gifted amateurs, and cranks. The book covers in detail heterodox and other contributions to the subject from outside academe. Yet this coverage comes at a cost. One complaint is that the authors have overemphasized the work of “radicals, out- siders, cranks, and heretics” and in the process omitted major themes in the development of economic analysis in Australia. The neglected contributions include the development of the computable general equilibrium models to ana- lyze commercial policy, Australia’s system of centralized wage-fixing, and the contributions of agricultural economists. The counsel of perfection is that an author should be frank about (or at least implicitly conscious of ) the way in which his or her ideological position colors the analysis, or try to be as objective as possible. Warren Samuels says that we should attempt to explain and interpret history with minimal ideological content, and without any intention to advance a political agenda, or without legitimizing and privileging any particular school of thought. Irrespective of these good intentions, others such as Martin Bronfenbrenner saw Samuels as an unmitigated critic of neoclassicism! Is quality history of thought produced by heterodox economists? History of thought has always been used by economists (either trained in history of thought or not) in theoretical debates about mainstream economics. Blaug (2001, pp. 154– 5) documents the examples of J. M. Keynes and Robert Lucas. Persuasion in- volves appeal to historical argument. But is an article on how Hayek would have analyzed the process of Eastern European transition, or how Minsky would have explained the Asian Crisis, a contribution to historical scholarship? Roy Weintraub would say no. Donald Walker (1988) would agree, but for different reasons. For Walker, the factor that determines whether or not economic writings are treated as part of the history of thought is not how long ago they were written but the approach of the person who is dealing with them. Walker proceeds to explain that an economist treats either present-day writings or older ones as history of thought when he examines them in order to establish their characteristics, inter- prets them, and evaluates them. He may or may not relate current doctrine to past doctrine, or examine past doctrine to see how it evolved into a subsequent RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 663 state. But the historian “does not attack the doctrine as part of a debate over what current economic theory should be. Nor does he incorporate the doctrine into a new theory or modify it. The historian of economic thought cannot add to the unalterable body of past writings with which he deals. In contrast the contributor to current theory changes the subject on which he is writing so as to produce a new body of theory” (Walker, 1988, pp. 99–100). The issues raised in this section are not straightforward and often bewitched by terminological minefields, which we now enter. 39.4 A TORTUOUS MAZE OF TERMINOLOGY Let us start with the term “orthodox” economics. This term is often used inter- changeably with mainstream, modern, or neoclassical economics. It is question- able how useful these terms are, especially the latter one. Colander (2000) argues that neoclassical economics is not synonymous with modern mainstream eco- nomics. Even when Veblen coined the term, “it was not meant as a description of mainstream economics” (p. 131). Certain aspects of neoclassical economics remain as part of modern economics, but “modern economics is fundamentally different from neoclassical economics” (p. 133). Arguably, neoclassicism has the following characteristics: methodological individualism, subjective utility, rational economic man, efficient resource allocation, a general equilibrium conception of the economy, and a focus on the margin. Modern economics, says Colander, has departed from strict adherence to these modeling attributes. Hence we should stop using the term “neoclassical.” Even more recently, John Davis (2002) has foreshadowed the “death” of “mainstream” economics. The mainstream is not a unified research program: many strands exist within the mainstream, such as game theory, and experimental and evolutionary economics. Unlike the neo- classical program of old, these are fragmented research programs. What holds these programs together is a shared methodology. Furthermore, the mainstream only achieves its prominence in a small set of North American hierarchical institutions. If we leave the maze of the present, even in earlier times it is sometimes difficult to locate a ruling orthodoxy. Morgan and Rutherford (1998) show this clearly for the interwar period in America. Pluralism was the order of the day. There was no hegemony of method. Furthermore, a school or individual may be orthodox at one point in history and heterodox the next, and eventually return to the fold. Take Hayek, for example (Cockett, 1994). The definition of heterodox economics is another bugbear. Colander (2000) again treads where angels fear to go. He lists several leading economists who have worked outside the orthodox framework, but they would not be regarded as “heterodox.” He suggests that “If the term heterodox is to be considered mean- ingful, it should be defined as an approach to problems that is not accepted as legitimate. Thus, my litmus test of heterodox economists is their ability to get jobs at major graduate schools. Marxists and Institutionalist economists are heterodox economists” (p. 137). Note how centered on North American and how ahistorical this demarcation principle is. It apparently means that almost all historians of 664 J. LODEWIJKS thought are heterodox. In fact, most of the economics profession would be heterodox, as there are only a small number of top graduate schools – perhaps 20, or as many as 50? Warren Samuels at Michigan State would not be classified as heterodox, even though he was long-time editor of the Journal of Economic Issues. What about Joan Robinson, Piero Sraffa, or Geoffrey Harcourt at Cam- bridge, or Hayek at the London School of Economics. Were they not heterodox? Colander further confuses issues by attempting to characterize the central attri- butes of modern economics. We are told that content does not define modern economics. The modeling approach to problems is the central element of modern economics. So far, so good. Then he states that the “modelling is not seen as an end in itself; there is a continual discussion of the need to empirically test, and the formal modelling is undertaken in large part to make the models empirically testable, and applicable to policy, with formal statistical techniques” so that “the major thrust of modern economics is on formal empirical testing of the models” (Colander, 2000, pp. 137, 140). Hutchison, Stigler, Blaug, and a host of comment- ators would take issue with these statements. In the very next article in the same journal issue in which Colander published his piece, we have a distinguished historian of thought, A. W. Coats, leading a round table on heterodox economics. Coats (2000) says that economics is such a heterogeneous discipline that, alongside the formalist uniformity, “there is also within the subject a number of dissenting or deviant doctrinal schools, rival methodological approaches, and innovative developments designed to remedy its defects and/or overcome its limitations” (p. 145). Many of the criticisms and remedies come from prominent economists with impeccable professional cred- entials. Their criticisms threaten the discipline’s foundations and are a species of “orthodox subversion” (p. 146), and many are compatible with heterodoxy. He broadly defines heterodox as encompassing all nonorthodox ideas and approaches, including experimental, behavioral, social, and evolutionary economists. Coats lists the following as heterodox (that is, idiosyncratic, maverick, or deviant, but not necessarily dissident): George Akerlof, Robert Frank, Albert Hirschman, Mancur Olson, James Buchanan, Harvey Leibenstein, Thomas Schelling, Amartya Sen, Vernon Smith, Richard Thaler, and Oliver Williamson. Note that these eco- nomists are or were associated with “top” graduate schools! Roger Backhouse’s contribution to the round table is to provide a dividing line between dissent within orthodoxy and dissent from orthodoxy. He offers a very strict definition of heterodoxy. Economists are heterodox if they “self-consciously claim to be working in a way that does not fit in with the dominant way of doing economics, or to be offering an alternative that is incompatible with this.” They have different core beliefs about the economy, publish in their own journals, go to their own conferences, and cite fellow travelers. Backhouse says that real business cycle and new institutional economics fails at least some of these criteria, and that only Marxian, post-Keynesian, old institutionalist, radical, and Austrian economics satisfy all of the criteria (p. 149). Clearly, who is and who is not “heterodox” is a tricky issue, and will vary over time and space. Much of the discussion seems to implicitly assume that what now goes on in the “top” North American graduate schools defines orthodoxy. [...]... sizeable history- of- thought lists also have substantial heterodox listings or are aimed at a market (Japanese) that is more receptive to heterodoxy With respect to journals, do we consider refereed journal publication in the leading journals and the specialist history- of- thought journals, or do we also include the Cambridge Journal of Economics, the Journal of Economic Issues, the Journal of Austrian Economics,... some of its members do not even regard themselves as heterodox, but as part of the neoclassical tradition, because of shared aspects of a research program that is striving for universal explanation on the basis of marginal utility analysis Finally, one might think that the phrase “research in the history of economic thought would be clear-cut But is it research in economic thought or the history of economics?... have in the past To paraphrase Joan Robinson, we study the history of economics so as not to be fooled by historians of economic thought Note I would like to acknowledge the helpful comments made by Warren Samuels, John Davis, and Jeff Biddle on an earlier draft of this chapter Bibliography Blaug, M 1999: Misunderstanding classical economics: the Sraffian interpretation of the surplus approach History. .. results that are arguably “biased.” History done for the purpose of defending or criticizing some approach to economics is likely to be, as history, less reliable than, or inferior to, the work of an author who at least tries to maintain an objective or disinterested stance toward the material We would like to think that historians of thought would quickly pounce on any bias or lack of objectivity, as they... American historyof -thought meetings The methodologists have journals of their own – Economics and Philosophy and the Journal of Economic Methodology – and publish their work in quality mainstream journals The relevance of this approach for our craft is that there have been numerous attempts to apply ideas from the philosophy of science to the history of economics We can be brief here, as John Davis... vindicated, although each school will have a different account of why the program failed 39. 6 CONCLUDING REMARKS The history of economics can be used as defensive, critical, or neutral with reference to mainstream economics The influx of critics of modern economics into the craft reflects broader currents in the profession that relate to research funding and corporatization of universities History of thought. .. as RESEARCH IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT 667 policy papers using historical argument John Davis and Steve Medema have said that we need openness and inclusion, perhaps at some sacrifice to quality They would rather celebrate diversity than homogenize the field There is a place for all approaches – Mirowski, Blaug, Walker, and even Samuelson A key issue is whether there is a systematic bias in the. .. in the way in which a large number of historians of economics pursue their craft Is it ideologically based? Is the research motivated by a broader agenda of criticism of orthodoxy? Criticism may be used to reform the discipline or as a means to support alternative schools of thought To the extent that we do not work in the dominant mathematical discourse of the profession, what we do will have little... and McFarlane, B 1990: A History of Australian Economic Thought London: Routledge Hands, D W 2001: Review of Hutchison, On the Methodology of Economics and the Formalist Revolution Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 23(4), 536–40 668 J LODEWIJKS Harcourt, G C 2001: 50 Years a Keynesian and Other Essays New York: Palgrave Heilbroner, R L 1979: Modern economics as a chapter in the history of. .. historians of thought to pursue intellectual history and historical reconstruction according to the standards of historians? Should we abandon current debates and rational reconstructions? This would narrow participation in the field; membership would be less open Barriers to entry would inhibit many heterodox and other economists – although some wear multiple hats and can “do” quality history of thought as . Smith was the first history- of- thought text in the light of the Sraffian revolution. Sraffa’s “corn model” interpretation of Ricardo led to a rational reconstruction of the history of economics to. publication in the leading journals and the specialist history- of- thought journals, or do we also include the Cambridge Journal of Economics, the Journal of Economic Issues, the Journal of Austrian. opinionated account of the lives and theories of famous economists.” A related point is that these texts relate to the teaching of the history of economics, not research at the frontier of the sub-discipline.

Ngày đăng: 06/07/2014, 03:20

Từ khóa liên quan

Tài liệu cùng người dùng

Tài liệu liên quan