Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống
1
/ 11 trang
THÔNG TIN TÀI LIỆU
Thông tin cơ bản
Định dạng
Số trang
11
Dung lượng
182,61 KB
Nội dung
1
Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 2, No. 1, April 2005
WHY DOESFEMINISMMATTERTOAESTHETICS?
JOSHUA SHAW
PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY, ERIE
1. INTRODUCTION
Peter Lamarque recently reported on current trends in aesthetics in the Postgraduate Journal
of Aesthetics.
1
Noticeably absent from his list, however, is the emergence and acceptance of
feminist approaches in aesthetics, especially among analytic philosophers. Yet feminism is an
important movement, one that should have been included among those he discusses. Indeed,
my goal is to convince you that feminism should have made it onto Lamarque’s list. Rather than
criticize him, however, I want to use his oversight to ask why feminist philosophers working in
analytic aesthetics have trouble getting the recognition they deserve. My suggestion will be that
the specificity of feminist critiques in aesthetics is often what makes it difficult for philosophers to
appreciate their significance.
2
I will also argue that it is precisely because of this specificity that
feminism is a uniquely important movement in contemporary aesthetics.
1
Lamarque, 'Reflections on Current Trends in Aesthetics,' Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 1, No.
1., April 2004.
2
For now I would like to leave it somewhat ambiguous as to what I mean by 'the specificity of feminist
critiques in aesthetics.' Later in this essay I will suggest, however, that a unifying thread in feminist writings
in aesthetics is their effort to critique masculinist biases in the spheres of art and aesthetic experience. As
such, these writings often have highly particular focuses; they attempt to document masculinist privilege in
some particular artwork or in some particular cultural phenomenon.
2
JOSHUA SHAW
2. IS FEMINISM A TREND IN AESTHETICS?
3
Is feminism a trend in aesthetics? I believe it is. Feminist ideas are certainly not new to the art
world; artists and critics such as Judy Chicago, Nancy Spero, Lucy Lippard, and Linda Nochlin
have been reflecting on them since the rise of the women’s art movement in the late sixties and
early seventies. It has taken time, though, for philosophers to see themselves as having a role to
play in clarifying and evaluating ideas advanced by feminists. For example, Hypatia and The
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, two leading English-language journals on,
respectively, feminist philosophy and aesthetics, did not devote issues to feminist aesthetics until
1990.
4
These collections sparked a flurry of publications in the 1990s by professional
Anglophone philosophers on topics such as the exclusion of women artists from the canons of
art history, representations of women in art, and the role of gender in relation to art and
aesthetic experience.
5
Recently, Hypatia devoted a second issue to feminist aesthetics, one that
took stock of how feminist approaches had evolved in the decade since its original, landmark
publication. So feminism seems to be both a recent and burgeoning trend in aesthetics.
Indeed, much of the evidence Lamarque cites in his essay supports this claim. For example,
he notes that it is 'not fortuitous that in three of the recent collections on aesthetics, the
Routledge Companion to Aesthetics (2001), the Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics (2003)
and the Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics (2004) there are separate sections devoted to…
individual arts.'
6
This point can also be made of feminism. The Oxford Handbook of
3
It should be clear that I do not mean to suggest that feminism is faddish, or that it should not be taken
seriously, in referring to it as a 'trend.' The term 'trend' sometimes carries negative associations. I use it to
discuss feminism in this essay because Peter Lamarque uses it in 'Reflection on Current Trends in
Aesthetics.'
4
See Hilde Hein and Carolyn Korsmeyer, eds., Hypatia, Special Issue: Feminism and Aesthetics, Vol. 5, No.
2 (Spring, 1990); The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Special Issue: Feminism and Traditional
Aesthetics, Vol. 48, No. 4 (Autumn, 1990).
5
See Hilde Hein and Carolyn Korsmeyer, eds. Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective (Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press, 1993); Peg Brand and Carolyn Korsmeyer, eds., Feminism and Tradition in Aesthetics,
(University Park, PA; Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995); Kosrmeyer, 'Perceptions, Pleasures, Arts:
Considering Aesthetics,' Philosophy in a Feminist Voice: Critiques and Reconstructions; Brand, ed.,
Beauty Matters (Bloomington, IN; 2000); Korsmeyer, Gender and Aesthetics (New York: Routledge, 2004).
6
Lamarque, 'Reflections on Current Trends in Aesthetics,' Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 1, No. 1
3
JOSHUA SHAW
Aesthetics and the Routledge Companion to Aesthetics both include essays on feminist
aesthetics,
7
and it has become standard practice to include entries on feminism and
representative essays by feminists in aesthetics encyclopedias and introductory aesthetics
anthologies. Thus the most recent edition of Oxford University Press’s Encyclopedia of
Aesthetics includes entries on 'Feminism,' 'Feminism and Tradition,' 'Critiques of Feminist
Aesthetics,' and 'Feminist Art History,' and each of the following anthologies include essays on
feminism: Goldblatt’s and Brown’s Aesthetics: A Reader in Philosophy of the Arts (1997),
Feagin’s and Maynard’s Aesthetics (1998), and Neil’s and Ridley’s Arguing about Art
(2001).
It is also illuminating to contrast feminism with trends Lamarque depicts as topical.
Lamarque remarks on the growing interest in aesthetics with individual art forms.
8
I was
reminded when I read him, however, of John Passmore’s influential 1954 essay 'The Dreariness
of Aesthetics.' One of Passmore’s claims was that aesthetics had become an especially 'dreary'
branch of philosophy because aestheticians were too preoccupied with sweeping definitions of
art. He urged them instead to engage in 'an intensive study of the separate arts, carried out…
[with] much respect for real differences between the works of art themselves.'
9
Lamarque’s
remarks on the current interest in specific arts might be read as vindication at long last of
Passmore’s point. Yet recalling Passmore’s essay leads me to wonder about the aptness of
describing the current interest in individual arts as pioneering. If it was timely for him to
advocate specificity in the fifties, how innovative can it be for us to heed that call today? This is
not to deny that aestheticians have become more interested in specific art forms. My point is
that the rise of feminism in aesthetics looks all the more innovative when you contrast it with this
trend —when you notice that the first publications in this area by Anglophone philosophers were
little more than ten years ago, whereas Passmore urged us to dispense with sweeping theories of
art fifty years ago.
(April; 2004).
7
See, respectively, Mary Devereaux’s 'Feminist Aesthetics,' Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics, pp. 647 – 666,
and Sarah Worth’s 'Feminist Aesthetics,' Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, pp.437 – 446.
8
See Lamarque, 'Reflections on Current Trends,' Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, pp. 1-2.
9
Passmore, 'The Dreariness of Aesthetics,' Mind, Vol. 60, No. 239 (Jul., 1951), p. 335.
4
JOSHUA SHAW
Now I want to be careful in challenging Lamarque. His survey is not intended to be
exhaustive; he refers to it as a set of 'informal observations, neither comprehensive nor
systematic,' that he offers based on his experiences as editor of The British Journal of
Aesthetics. So my claim that feminism is a trend need not contradict him. He might also note
that this trend simply is not reflected in submissions to The British Journal of Aesthetics.
There may be differences between the British and American aesthetics communities, with
feminism enjoying greater popularity in the United States. These strike me as legitimate replies.
I find, though, that they deepen my puzzlement. Assume that feminism was not included in his
survey because few articles have been submitted to The British Journal of Aesthetics that
assess puzzles in aesthetics from a feminist perspective; this answer does not so much alleviate
as exacerbate my concern. I began by wondering whyfeminism was not included in
Lamarque’s essay given that it has, I believe, as great a claim to be a trend as those he
discusses. But if I am correct, why isn’t this trend reflected in the submissions to The British
Journal of Aesthetics? What makes it difficult for aestheticians in general, not just one
prominent aesthetician, to recognize feminism as a legitimate trend?
A tempting answer comes to mind. Feminist writings are often animated by a special
urgency. Consider what happens when a feminist notes how formalist theories of art lead us to
overlook women’s artistic achievements. Women often have been denied the same artistic
training and opportunities as men, and the only avenue of artistic expression available to them
often has been craft items, whose use-value makes it difficult to recognize them as art given a
formalist theory. The feminist’s point is not purely theoretical; she is not simply identifying a limit
in one theory of art. She is counteracting a pernicious bias. Feminist writings often proceed,
then, from the perspective that our habitual ways of talking about art are riddled with masculinist
biases, and feminists are inclined to view failures to acknowledge the extent to which women
have been excluded from the artworld not as innocent oversights but as manifestations of these
biases. So the temptation for someone like myself, who sees feminism as a key movement in
aesthetics, is to conjecture that the absence of any mention of feminism in Lamarques’s essay is
indicative of some larger masculinist bias at work in this essay.
Yet this criticism strikes me as unsatisfying. For one thing, it devolves too easily into ad
5
JOSHUA SHAW
hominem. It is also unhelpful. Again, assume that there have not been many feminist
submissions to The British Journal of Aesthetics. The provocative question this lack raises is
why there have been so few. Why do feminists find it difficult to see their work as suitably
'philosophic' to submit it to this journal? In particular, is there something about contemporary
analytic aesthetics that makes it difficult for feminists to see themselves as having insights to
contribute to this area? Attributing the dearth of feminist submissions to some masculinist bias in
its editorial practices dodges this question.
3. RETHINKING BEAUTIFICATION: ANN CAHILL ON DRESSING UP
I have a theory about this issue, but it will be helpful to first focus on an example to illustrate it.
Let me focus on a recent essay by Ann Cahill entitled 'Feminist Pleasure and Feminine
Beautification.' I choose this essay for two reasons. First, Cahill’s essay is a nice example of
the work currently being done in feminist aesthetics.
10
Second, we would not be surprised, I
think, to find her essay in an analytically oriented journal like The British Journal of Aesthetics
or The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
11
She presents what she calls a
'phenomenological analysis of a particular process of beautification.'
12
Yet her method is more
autobiographic than phenomenological. She reflects on what it was like to dress up for a
10
Cahill’s essay was recently published in a special issue of Hypatia (2003, Vol. 18, No. 4: 42-64) on feminist
aesthetics, the aim of which was to assess how feminist approaches had evolved since the landmark 1990
issue of Hypatia on this topic. Her essay is one of many essays in this volume to reappraise ideas put
forward by previous feminist aestheticians.
11
Professor Cahill might not agree with this assessment of her essay. She is one of the editors of the
Continental Feminism Reader (Lanham, Maryland; Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), and she might dispute my
characterization of her essay as analytic. I do not want to overstate my point. My claim is simply that it is
reasonable to think that her essay could be found in a more analytically-oriented aesthetics journal like The
British Journal of Aesthetics. I draw this conclusion for several reasons. First, her essay does not make
heavy use of technical terminology popular in contemporary continental philosophy. She makes passing
reference to Heidegger, but she does rely on more recent continental philosophers or continental feminists.
Finally, as I note above, her essay is not so much phenomenological, as she suggests, as autobiographic.
So while I can imagine a case being made for thinking of her essay as an example of continental philosophy,
it strikes me as reasonable that it could pass for analytic. I hasten to add that no value judgment is intended
in noting this distinction.
12
Cahill, 'Feminine Pleasure and Feminine Beautification,' Hypatia, p. 43.
6
JOSHUA SHAW
sister’s wedding. But it is not unheard of for analytic aestheticians to employ autobiography.
13
So her essay is both a nice example of contemporary feminist aesthetics and an essay we should
not be surprised to find in an analytically-oriented aesthetics journal. One way to pose my
question, then, would be to ask whether there is, nevertheless, anything in her essay that might
make it challenging for an analytic philosopher to accept it as philosophic. Knowing that we
should accept it as philosophic, is there anything that might make it difficult to appreciate it as
such?
Let me say more about Cahill’s argument. Her goal is to develop a subtler analysis of
beautification than those proposed by other feminists. Many feminists deplore the role beauty
plays in women’s lives. Beautification practices are, they argue, cruel and oppressive, for they
inevitably require women to capitulate to male ideals of beauty, and the considerable role they
play in women’s lives speaks to the thoroughness of women’s subjugation to these standards.
Cahill’s aim is to chart a more moderate position—one that neither uncritically denounces nor
uncritically accepts feminine beautification. Toward this goal, she reflects on the experience of
getting dressed up for a sister’s wedding. Her essay is rich, and I cannot do justice to the many
points she makes, but let me mention a few key theses.
One of her key insights is that the rituals women perform in preparing for special occasions,
such as weddings, differ from everyday beautification. Most feminists to have written on this
topic have focused on the dietary and cosmetic practices women perform on a daily bases. A
woman’s focus in these cases, however, Cahill suggests, is not so much beauty as complying
with a 'cultural necessity.'
14
By contrast, women seem to directly reflect on their appearance as
an aesthetic project when they undertake the extensive task of, say, getting dressed up for a
wedding or a prom. The routines they perform in preparing for such 'special occasions' seem to
constitute a clearer indicator, therefore, of the role beauty plays in their lives.
Cahill makes several provocative points based on this insight. For example, she notes that
13
See for example Peter Kivy’s 'Jokes are a Laughing Matter,' The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism,
Vol. 61:1, Winter; 2003. Kivy ends his essay by recalling what it was like as a young philosopher to attend
meetings of the American Philosophical Association and felt alienated by the jokes told at them.
14
Cahill, 'Feminist Pleasure and Feminine Beautification,' Hypatia, p. 44.
7
JOSHUA SHAW
the decision to adopt an aesthetic standpoint toward oneself is more deliberate than many
feminists have assumed. Getting 'dressed up' is a luxury one permits oneself on rare occasions.
Far from mechanically capitulating to masculine expectations about appearance, getting dressed
up involves a deliberate suspension of everyday cultural expectations about appearance in which
one adopts something more like a disinterested, purely aesthetic standpoint toward one’s
appearance. Cahill also notes that women typically engage in beautification practices apart from
men, in the company of other women. Getting dressed up for a wedding or prom is
collaborative enterprise, with women helping each other dress up, alternatively shifting between
being co-audiences and co-creators of their appearances as artistic projects. Thus feminist
dismissals of beauty seem too crude. Far from requiring women to mechanically surrender to a
male audience’s expectations, beautification in its purest cases involves a voluntary decision to
take up a disinterested standpoint toward oneself and to share this standpoint with other women
whom one regards as co-authors of one’s appearance as an artistic project.
4. WHY HAVE THERE BEEN NO GREAT WOMEN AESTHETICIANS?
15
More could be said about Cahill’s essay. My interest, though, is not her essay’s details but
what it reveals about why it is difficult to see oneself as a feminist and a philosopher. I
suggested that her essay is a good example of the work being done in feminist aesthetics and
that we should not be surprised to find it an analytically-oriented journal like The British
Journal of Aesthetics. If I am right, what does her essay reveal about why it is nonetheless
difficult to think of oneself as a feminist aesthetician?
My hunch is that some philosophers would see her essay as too anecdotal. Her claims about
beauty rely on her analysis of her sisters’ experiences as they prepared for their wedding. Yet
15
The title of this subsection is a pun on art historian Linda Nochlin’s groundbreaking 1971 essay 'Why
Have There Been No Great Women Artists?' Nochlin argued, among other things, that the traditional idea of
fine art had led art historians to overlook the artistic accomplishment of women. Similarly, my claim in this
section is not that there have not been any important figures in feminist aesthetics but that there is a bias in
our traditional idea of aesthetics, our expectations about what it means to work in this area, that keeps us
from recognizing feminists as legitimate philosophers of art.
8
JOSHUA SHAW
counterexamples come to mind for them. For example, why assume that dressing up
necessarily involves a voluntary break with everyday cultural expectations about appearance?
Why not view it as an involuntary intensification of these expectations? Cahill makes it sound
as if her sisters were engaged in a kind of Kantian free play of imagination while they dressed
up, but presumably it would not have been okay to paint their faces teal in the name of
disinterested aesthetic self-contemplation. So why not interpret dressing up as amplification of
already demanding strictures about appearance? And why conclude from the fact that women
dress up together that a uniquely feminist community is thereby created? Women’s fashion
magazines contain few pictures of men; here too, then, we have a community focused on
feminine beauty that is comprised almost entirely of women. Yet why not interpret the fact that
women comprise the bulk of these magazines’ readerships as evidence of the prevalence of the
'male gaze?' Why not see it as regrettable that women should be presented as objects of beauty
in both men’s and women’s magazines?
Now let me be clear: my aim is not to fault Cahill.
16
My point is that some philosophers
might dismiss her essay because it is so focused on one specific event. Her claims about
beatification may be true to what she and her sisters felt as they prepared for their wedding, but
counterexamples come to mind for her claims, and some will conclude, I submit, that she is not
really doing philosophy so much as a kind of autobiography or ethnography. Indeed, she herself
sometimes voices this worry:
As I examine one particular experience of communal feminine beautifying for its meaning for
feminine subjectivity, my analysis is of course limited by the particularity of that experience.
Indeed, the women who will provide the material for my analysis speak and act from a highly
particularized location, one marked, among other factors, their race (white), class status
(upper), education (advanced), and familial size and structure (large and traditionally
nuclear).
17
Cahill here acknowledges the diversity of experiences that women can have with respect to
16
Indeed, she offers a plausible counterargument to my second criticism. See Cahill, 'Feminist Pleasure and
Feminine Beautification,' Hypatia, p. 60, for her remarks on the tendency among feminists to exaggerate the
authority and prevalence of the so-called 'male gaze.'
17
Cahill, 'Feminist Pleasure and Feminine Beautification,' Hypatia, p. 44.
9
JOSHUA SHAW
beauty based on factors such as race and class. But a philosopher of a different stripe might
read this passage as evidence that her essay is too 'particularized' to have conclusions of broad
philosophic import. Her essay may be interesting for what it says about how women of a
particular racial and economic group feel about dressing up, but we cannot draw any general
conclusions based on her reflections, unlike, say, a more abstract essay on the ontology of
beautification.
I focus on Cahill’s essay, but my sense is that such specificity is common in feminist
aesthetics. Six of the ten scholarly essays
18
published in Hypatia’s recent issue on feminist
aesthetics focus on specific artists (Jenny Saville, Titian, Virginia Woolf), specific groups of
artists (Catholic women artists), or specific cultural phenomena (dressing up for weddings,
Venus and Serena Williams’s tennis outfits). A similar pattern can be found in Hein’s and
Korsmeyer’s Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective, which was based on the landmark 1990
issue of Hypatia on feminist aesthetics. Several of this collection’s essays focus on specific
artists (Georgia Okeefe), groups of artists (contemporary black women novelists), or specific
cultural artefacts and phenomena (depictions of feminists in suffragist cartoons). A noteworthy
feature of feminist aesthetics, then, is its specificity. Feminist aesthetics is perhaps best defined,
as Mary Devereaux notes, as a 'diverse family of theories, approaches, and models of criticism
united by their resistance to "male" privilege and domination in the sphere of art and aesthetic
experience.'
19
One of the main ways feminists resist male privilege, in turn, is by critiquing
specific artworks and cultural trends. To be a feminist is, we might say, to be committed to
weeding out masculinist biases, and to accomplish this task a feminist typically needs to
document their presence in specific artworks or cultural phenomena.
So my suggestion is that philosophers have difficulty appreciating feminist aesthetics as
philosophy because of its specificity. But if I am correct, then we have all the more reason to
respect it as a trend in aesthetics. One of Lamarque’s provocative claims is that the current
18
I do not include Patricia Locke’s poem, Joanna Frueh’s commentary on her performance art, my annotated
bibliography, or Estella Lauter’s and Flo Leibowitz’s book reviews in this list. I hasten to add that no value
judgment is intended in separating out these texts as 'non-scholarly.'
19
I borrow this definition from Mary Devereaux. See Devereaux, 'Feminist Aesthetics,' Oxford Handbook of
Aesthetics, p. 647.
10
JOSHUA SHAW
interest in individual arts may lead to a crisis in aesthetics:
[T]he worry is that aesthetics then loses that great aspiration of philosophy, however derided,
to be universal and timeless… In other words, the more abstract the subject matter the more
universal are the findings likely to be; an analysis of truth or meaning or ontology or
symbolism or fictionality is inherently less likely to be culture bound than discussions of
impressionist painting, avant garde film or the realist novel… [L]et me describe the tension
like this. The more abstract the subject matter of aesthetics… the more respect aesthetics is
likely to gain in the broader philosophical community…. However, aesthetics of this kind
wins this respectability at a price, for it loses much of its distinctness… and is in danger too of
losing touch with the art forms it purports to analyse and the practitioners of these forms.
20
Aesthetics has always been a misfit branch of philosophy, often seeming too close to art
criticism for philosophers in more abstract areas, like metaphysics and epistemology, to take
seriously. The growing interest in individual arts does not bode well, in turn, for our efforts to
win philosophic respectability. We aestheticians had a hard enough time winning respect when
we were obsessed with identifying necessary and sufficient conditions for an object’s qualifying
as art; it will be all the more difficult now that we have abandoned this project in focused
meditations on impressionist painting, avant garde film, and realist novels.
But in that case feminism’s struggle to win recognition in aesthetics mirrors the problem
aesthetics faces with respect to philosophy in general. Just as aestheticians struggle to convince
philosophers their work has broad implications for other areas of philosophy, so too feminists
have struggled to convince aestheticians their work has broad implications for aesthetics. If this
comparison is fair, then feminists may have insights to offer aestheticians. If Lamarque is
correct, aesthetics now faces a crisis with respect to the relationship between the particular and
the universal. On the one hand, what distinguishes aesthetics, what keeps it, in Passmore’s
words, from being dreary, is its specificity, its ability to impart the thrill that comes from
appreciating a great book, painting, or piece of music. On the other hand, the more aesthetics
contents itself with this particularity the less it seems like philosophy. So the challenge is to
explicate this gap between the particular and the universal—to show how conclusions of broad
import flow out of careful analyses of specific artworks or aesthetic experiences. But feminists
20
Lamarque, 'Reflections on Current Trends,' Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, p. 2.
[...]... increasingly coming to conclude that there was no such thing as a single feminine nature Hein saw value in such postmodern critiques of essentialism but worried about their relativism Aesthetics, she hoped, might offer an alternative The challenge feminists faced was to respect the full diversity of women’s life experiences while identifying conclusions of broad significance to feminists trying to oppose masculinist... analyses of specific artworks But it is precisely because feminists have grappled with this dilemma since they began to publish in aesthetics that their work should matterto aesthetics Hein, 'Refining Feminist Theory: Lessons from Aesthetics,' Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective (Bloomington, IN; Indiana University Press, 1993), pp 4 – 5 21 11 ... aestheticians have always sought to elaborate general claims about art based on their firsthand experience of particular artworks So Hein’s hope was that aesthetics might serve as a model for how to theorize about the particular without sacrificing the ambition for the universal The situation may now be reversed If Lamarque is correct, the challenge aestheticians face is to show how claims of broad import... laboured with this dilemma, I suggest, since they first began to publish in aesthetics Indeed, I find it helpful to close by juxtaposing my quotation from Peter Lamarque with an observation Hilde Hein made in one the first publications in feminist aesthetics: I shall argue that because aesthetics has never entirely betrayed or abandoned its openness to all kinds and grades of experiences, it remains… a model .
Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics, Vol. 2, No. 1, April 2005
WHY DOES FEMINISM MATTER TO AESTHETICS?
JOSHUA SHAW
PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIVERSITY, ERIE. raises is
why there have been so few. Why do feminists find it difficult to see their work as suitably
'philosophic' to submit it to this journal?