1. Trang chủ
  2. » Luận Văn - Báo Cáo

Psychology is still a problematic science and the public knows it

2 8 0

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

THÔNG TIN TÀI LIỆU

Thông tin cơ bản

Định dạng
Số trang 2
Dung lượng 70,81 KB

Nội dung

American Psychologist, 63, 146 –159 doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.63.3.146 Lilienfeld, S O (2012) Public skepticism of psychology: Why many people perceive the study of human behavior as unscientific American Psychologist, 67, 111–129 doi: 10.1037/a0023963 Tryon, W W (2009) Missing mechanism information American Psychologist, 64, 273–274 doi:10.1037/a0015348 Tryon, W W (2012, June 11) A connectionist network approach to psychological science: Core and corollary principles Review of General Psychology Advance online publication doi:10.1037/a0027135 Correspondence concerning this comment should be addressed to Warren W Tryon, Department of Psychology, Fordham University, 441 E Fordham Road, Dealy Hall, Bronx, NY 10458-5198 E-mail: wtryon@fordham.edu DOI: 10.1037/a0030084 Psychology Is Still a Problematic Science and the Public Knows It Thomas Teo York University According to the philosophers of science Hempel and Oppenheim (1948), who were cited appropriately by Lilienfeld (February–March 2012) in his article, scientific explanations serve to answer “why” questions Clarifying the logic of explanations in the sciences, they developed famously the notion that phenomena can be explained (using deduction) by means of general laws and by means of certain antecedent conditions According to Hempel and Oppenheim, the question of why the part of an oar that is under water appears bent upward to an observer in a rowboat can be explained by the law of refraction, by the law that water is optically denser than air and by reference to the fact that part of the oar is indeed in the water Here is not the space to discuss the intricacies and complexities of scientific explanations, because my point is more illustrative Lilienfeld’s (2012) subtitle (“Why Many People Perceive the Study of Human Behavior as Unscientific”) can easily be translated into the question “Why Do Many People Perceive the Study of Human Behavior as Unscientific?” But whereas Hempel and Oppenheim (1948) were able to explain a physical phenomenon by moving from the explanans to the explanandum via logical deduction, and whereas their explanans contained general laws and specific antecedent conditions, Lilienfeld (2012) could not rely on general laws or even statistical facts to provide a scientific explanation for this question What is evident from all we know from the philosophy of science is that Lilienfeld offered us an interpretation Although Lilienfeld provided good arguments and good reasons for the explanandum (e.g., why the public is skeptical toward psychology), citing studies and data, he clearly did not provide a deductive-nomological explanation in the sense of Hempel and Oppenheim or in the sense of the natural sciences Indeed, providing interpretations for complex issues of mental life is characteristic in the discipline of psychology Looking at some of the most important studies in the history of psychology, one can easily see that psychologists provide scientific interpretations rather than scientific explanations It should be emphasized that interpretations are important: They make data understandable, they are conveyed to a readership or audience (scientific or public), and they are needed for grasping complex psychological problems, including the issue that Lilienfeld (2012) raised Thus, it would be unreasonable to assume that other psychologists would answer Lilienfeld’s question in similar ways (he listed eight sources) For example, as a historian and theoretician of psychology, I would suggest that some of the answers lie in the subject matter of psychology, within a limited epistemology, and in the social function of psychology This means that I would give primacy to the analysis of the discipline of psychology, which I label as still problematic (see also Woodward & Ash, 1982) (a) Lilienfeld (2012) articulated and described some surface phenomena very well, but ontological analyses demand an understanding of the nature of the discipline of psychology History has demonstrated that psychology is as much a human science as it is a natural science Pioneers of psychology, from Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911) and Abraham Maslow (1908 –1970) to contemporaries such as Amedeo Giorgi or Kenneth Gergen, to name a few, understood that very well Thus, it is unclear why Lilienfeld restricted his quest to the “Study of Human Behavior” (as in his subtitle) when it is clear that psychology as a discipline has embraced in its history different definitions of its subject matter, including consciousness, mental life, experience, subjectivity, behavior, the mind, the brain, and so on All of these subject matters have a natural-scientific but also a human-scientific dimension Memory can be studied through neuroscience but also through phenomenology or psychoanalysis Equally important, the public is interested in the December 2012 ● American Psychologist natural-scientific foundation of memory but particularly in the personal, subjective meaning of memory embedded in history and culture Academic psychology needs to address both needs (instead of leaving this to pop psychology) (b) In terms of epistemology, primacy should be given to the subject matter of psychology, or to the problems or topics for which psychologists develop methodologies and methods that justice to psychological problems Rather than privileging one set of methodologies or methods (e.g., the experiment), psychologists need to open their studies to the plurality of methods, quantitative or qualitative, and to the limitations of all of them Instead of a celebratory selling of goods to the public, I recommend knowledge about the limitations of psychological methods, modesty when making generalizations, and most of all, honesty about the contingencies of knowledge produced in psychological research Psychologists often provide interpretations that may be dependent on theory, history, and culture When research does not have immediate relevance to the public, we should address that rather than make promises about applications that we cannot keep Sometimes it will be necessary to admit that a study, working with isolated variables, may not have any reallife applications at all When admitting that interpretations are part of psychologists’ scientific life, we should discuss how we ensure that psychologists provide good interpretations of empirical evidence This requires academic training in interpretative competencies (Teo, 2008) (c) We cannot deny that many psychological issues have political-ethical meanings Suggesting that we can be completely neutral when it comes to hot-button issues in our historically and culturally contingent society, such as gay marriage, racism, parenting practices, gender differences, torture, mental illness, and so on, would be misleading The public has developed good intuitions about the nexus of human sciences and politics and understands that academics come from “somewhere.” The public also understands, although I not disagree with the misunderstandings that Lilienfeld (2012) enumerated, that psychology is not like physics, engineering, or medicine Here, I suggest an extension of honesty about the historical, cultural, and personal limitations of psychological knowledge and interpretations: Academic and public self-reflexivity would be an antidote to the myth of value-neutrality, and I not think it would weaken the discipline (see Morawski, 2005) Instead of presenting psychological research as final and as transcendent of culture and history, we need to 807 present psychological knowledge as contingent given the evolving and sometimes ideologically laden nature of the subject matter (d) Psychology has been an impressively successful discipline in North America, Europe, and many other parts of the world The process of psychologization, the fact that more and more areas of human existence—from education, industry, the military, the economy, legal and health systems, to society and politics—are understood in terms of psychological categories and theories can be identified as our success But with regard to the psychologization of public life—from discussions on national intelligence at the beginning of the 20th century, to the psychological contributions in Brown v Board of Education in the middle of the 20th century, to the notion of empathy deficits that President Obama evokes—the public also has a right to know about critical assessments of psychology from within the discipline (Slife, Reber, & Richardson, 2005; Teo, 2005) The psychologization of everyday life also demonstrates that the categories of psychology are not the same as those in the natural sciences (Danziger, 1997) One important feature that makes psychological concepts different is the evaluative looping effects (Hacking, 1994) that psychological categories evoke Psychology is applied in the public sphere through concepts or ideas developed in academia (e.g., IQ, emotional intelligence, extraversion, pathological grief, attribution style, the notion that brains are not wired correctly) But the application of these terms in the public sphere changes the public in that a different type of reflection occurs when the public uses these concepts in their self-understanding and in the formation of their identities—and when psychologists rediscover these entities in their research There exist ongoing looping effects between academic psychology and the public, and psychologists need to study and understand this dialectical interconnection REFERENCES Danziger, K (1997) Naming the mind: How psychology found its language London, England: Sage Hacking, I (1994) The looping effects of human kinds In D Sperber, D Premack, & A J Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary approach (pp 351–382) Oxford, England: Clarendon Press Hempel, C G., & Oppenheim, P (1948) Studies in the logic of explanation Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175 doi:10.1086/286983 Lilienfeld, S O (2012) Public skepticism of psychology: Why many people perceive the study of human behavior as unscientific 808 View publication stats American Psychologist, 67(2), 111–129 doi: 10.1037/a0023963 Morawski, J G (2005) Reflexivity and the psychologist History of the Human Sciences, 18(4), 77–105 doi:10.1177/0952695105058472 Slife, B D., Reber, J S., & Richardson, F C (2005) Critical thinking about psychology: Hidden assumptions and plausible alternatives Washington, DC: American Psychological Association Teo, T (2005) The critique of psychology: From Kant to postcolonial theory New York, NY: Springer Teo, T (2008) From speculation to epistemological violence in psychology: A critical-hermeneutic reconstruction Theory & Psychology, 18(1), 47– 67 doi:10.1177/0959354307086922 Woodward, W., & Ash, M G (Eds.) (1982) The problematic science: Psychology in nineteenth-century thought New York, NY: Praeger Correspondence concerning this comment should be addressed to Thomas Teo, Department of Psychology, York University, 4700 Keele Street, Toronto, Ontario M3J 1P3, Canada E-mail: tteo@yorku.ca DOI: 10.1037/a0031015 Further Sources of Our Field’s Embattled Public Reputation Scott O Lilienfeld Emory University In my article on public skepticism toward psychology (Lilienfeld, February–March 2012), I delineated eight reasons why many laypersons are dubious of our field’s scientific status I argued that although some of these sources (e.g., hindsight bias, the illusion of understanding) reflect public misunderstandings regarding the application of science to psychological questions, others (e.g., our field’s reluctant embrace of evidence-based clinical practices) reflect professional psychology’s failure to uphold rigorous scientific standards I was gratified to read these three stimulating commentaries, if only because they suggest that my article accomplished its principal aim: to engender thoughtful debate concerning the sources of, and remedies for, psychology’s problematic scientific status in the public eye The authors all noted significant points of consensus with my analysis but also identified areas in which they found my coverage to be incomplete or inaccurate I welcome these constructive criticisms and address each in turn I thank Newman, Bakina, and Tang (2012, this issue) for directing me to a source of public skepticism toward psychology that I had neglected: the fundamental attribution error (FAE) They con- jectured that because of the FAE, many laypersons are suspicious of standard social psychological explanations of behavior in the media, which emphasize situational influences These attributions, Newman et al contended, are readily perceived by the public as excusing unethical actions Newman et al drew on data (e.g., Newman & Bakina, 2009) demonstrating that after undergraduate participants read descriptions of studies that highlight situational rather than dispositional influences on immoral behavior (e.g., cheating, domestic abuse), they view the researchers who penned the descriptions as attempting to absolve individuals of responsibility for their actions If these results generalize to real-world settings, they could imply that many laypersons perceive psychologists, especially social psychologists, as “bleeding hearts” (Newman & Bakina, 2009, p 269) who are reluctant to hold bad actors to account for their misdeeds Newman et al (2012) additionally reported evidence that respondents are less likely to attribute what we might term “exculpatory intent” to investigators when the written accounts of the study accord roughly equal weight to situational and dispositional factors I find Newman et al.’s (2012) hypothesis to be worthwhile and intriguing, and I offer two friendly amendments to their friendly commentary First, I wonder whether participants in these studies were in essence behaving as “implicit Bayesians” when drawing inferences regarding researchers’ motives and views In everyday life, individuals who frequently invoke situational influences when explaining others’ unethical behavior (e.g., “The soldier followed the general’s orders because he felt he had no choice”) may indeed be more likely than other individuals to be attempting to condone it If so, these participants may be at least partly justified in their conclusions regarding the researchers’ intentions Second, although the FAE is undeniably an erroneous conclusion in certain instances, it probably reflects the overgeneralization of a broadly accurate propensity to perceive traitlike consistencies in individuals across situations (Funder, 1987) Indeed, at times social psychologists have gone too far in neglecting dispositional influences on behavior, as witnessed by efforts to minimize the role of individual differences in accounting for the deplorable behavior of approximately 10 U.S soldiers during the 2004 Abu Ghraib prison scandal (Donnellan, Fraley, & Krueger, 2007) A meta-analysis of over 25,000 studies comprising more than million participants revealed that the mean effect size of dispositional influences on behavior (r ϭ 19) is December 2012 ● American Psychologist ... Europe, and many other parts of the world The process of psychologization, the fact that more and more areas of human existence—from education, industry, the military, the economy, legal and health... criticisms and address each in turn I thank Newman, Bakina, and Tang (2012, this issue) for directing me to a source of public skepticism toward psychology that I had neglected: the fundamental... in their research There exist ongoing looping effects between academic psychology and the public, and psychologists need to study and understand this dialectical interconnection REFERENCES Danziger,

Ngày đăng: 12/10/2022, 11:00

TÀI LIỆU CÙNG NGƯỜI DÙNG

TÀI LIỆU LIÊN QUAN

w